Notes to Kurt Gödel

1. Though of course Gödel disagreed with many aspects of the Hilbert program, most notably with the thought that mathematics could be formally reconstructed in a content free manner.

2. Reprinted with a facing English translation in Gödel 1986. Henceforth all references to Gödel's papers will be to those as appear in his Collected Works, Volumes I to V. In particular all page references, as well as the numbering scheme for Gödel's papers, refer to that of the Collected Works. (So for example Gödel's paper "On intuitionistic arithmetic and number theory" is referred to below as 1933e, the number of it in volume I of the Collected Works, Gödel 1986.) In relevant cases the bibliography will cite original publication data as well.

3. According to the documents, the Ministry for Domestic and Cultural Affairs recommended against granting Gödel the Dozentur, on grounds of his having a political stance they termed "doubtful." See Sigmund 2006.

4. Though according to Menger, Leibniz was an important interest of Gödel's already in the 1930s.

5. See below for a discussion of Gödel's adoption of the phenomenological world view. For the relation between phenomenology and Leibniz as Gödel saw it see van Atten and Kennedy 2003.

6. Though some credit Bolzano's "Wissenschaftslehre" (Bolzano 1992) with the first statement of the question. See the introduction by Wang to Skolem's Selected Works in (Skolem 1970).

7. For the history of this theorem see Zach 1999.

8. Skolem himself referred to the fact that set theory has countable models as the‘relativity in set theory.’

9. See von Neumann 2005. Von Neumann is referring to the meeting on Logicism, Finitism and Intuitionism which took place in Königsberg in September of 1930, at which Gödel announced his First Incompleteness Theorem during a roundtable discussion on foundations.

10. Gödel uses the word ‘recursive’ in place of primitive recursive. For a definition of the terms ‘recursive’ and ‘primitive recursive’ see Rogers 1967. The use of recursive functions apparently goes back to Grassman, see p. 147 of Wang 1957.

11. Gödel uses the notation B(x,y) for Prf(x,y).

12. Gödel uses the notation Bew(y) for Prov(y).

13. ‘Jetzt, Mengenlehre!’—and now, [on to] set theory!—Gödel is alleged to have said around that time (see p.128 of Wang 1993, as well as Dawson 1997.) Gödel's interest in set theory may have begun to develop as early as 1928 when he requested at the library the volume containing Skolem's Helsinki lecture. Dawson mentions that in 1930 Gödel requested works by Fraenkel (Einleitung in die Mengenlehre, in which Gödel will have noticed Fraenkel's skepticism about Hilbert's attempted proof of the continuum hypothesis), von Neumann, and the paper in which Hilbert had put the problem of deciding the continuum hypothesis on the agenda of twentieth century mathematics.

14. For Gödel's reaction to Cohen's result see his September 1966 letter to Church in Gödel 2003a.

15. Of course Hilbert attempted to prove the CH, not just prove its consistency with the axioms of ZF or ZFC.

16. Such as: α < β implies LαLβ

17. For a discussion of Gödel's views on the absolute consistency of the Axiom of Constructibility see Kennedy and van Atten 2004.

18. Gödel's study of Leibniz took place principally from 1943 to 1946, see below.

19. There is some difficulty in making the notion "the largeness of V" precise. This is because adding sets can either collapse cardinals or increase the continuum; so adding sets in itself may lead to self-contradictory information about the continuum. See for example Foreman 1998.

20. Gödel remarks in a footnote to this passage that the notion of provability by any means imaginable is perhaps ‘too sweeping.’ Nevertheless, this does not affect the basic distinction that Gödel wishes to make, between the formal and informal notions of provability.

21. But see Troelstra's critical remarks in his introduction to the paper in Gödel 1995, having to do with the question whether, for the intuitionist, the Dialectica interpretation represents a genuine epistemological advance over the so-called Heyting/Kolmogorov proof interpretation.

22. Gödel was to find support for this view in Husserl, who also rejected the notion that a science of concepts should be mathematical in nature, or similar to any empirical science. As Husserl remarked in Ideen, about the project of developing phenomenology, "We are at the beginning…no science can help us."

23. The question whether its truth or falsity can be verified by a person is a separate one, and in fact Gödel often expressed the thought that we have only a "partial view" of sets and their properties.

Notes to the Supplements

Notes to Did the Incompleteness Theorems Refute Hilbert's Program?

1. For example, Bezboruah and Sheperdson proved (1976) the second incompleteness theorem for Q (essentially induction free arithmetic), and Wilkie & Paris proved (1987) that even the much stronger theory IΔ0 + exp does not prove its standard formulation of Q's consistency. But neither of these consistency statements can be said to be intensionally correct. And therefore it is not clear that the second theorem holds in its general form for Q. In fact, Q is such a weak theory, it is not clear that a semantically contentful statement of consistency can be formulated for Q at all.

A surprising result of Pavel Pudlák's undercuts this view. As a response to the Bezboruah and Sheperdson result, Pudlák gives (1996) an intensionally correct consistency statement for Robinson's theory Q, which Q fails to prove. The theorem states that for every consistent theory T extending Q, and for every cut J(x) in T, TConJT. Moreover, the arithmetization of syntax relativized to J satisfies all the relevant intensionality criteria. Therefore the second theorem can be said to hold for Q after all.

More recently, Curtis Franks takes up the issue of the second incompleteness theorem for weak arithmetic theories in his 2009, challenging Pudláak's argument that an intensionally adequate proof predicate can be given for Q. Any proof predicate which aspires to intensional correctness, he argues, should be formulated along the lines of Kreisel's no-counterexample construction, and therefore must involve the concept of Herbrand provability. Herbrand proofs are propositional proofs, and these are computationally simpler; also a game semantics can be given which relativizes in a natural way to the computational strength of the theory in question. But because the concepts of Herbrand provability and provability separate in weak theories, the question whether there is an intensionally adequate version of the Second Incompleteness Theorem for Robinson's Q remains open.

Notes to Gödel's Turn to Phenomenology

1. Gödel is very much following Husserl here. The matter is discussed in some detail in pp. 443-446 of van Atten and Kennedy 2003.

Notes to An Argument About the Content of Mathematics

1. Gödel readily drew philosophical conclusions from the First Incompleteness Theorem. He he seems to have been slower in applying the Second Theorem.

2. Regarding the acceptability of inductive methods Gödel remarks in the Gibbs lecture, for example, that, if one is a realist about mathematical objects then inductive methods become not less but more acceptable. See p. 313 of Gödel 1995.

Copyright © 2015 by
Juliette Kennedy <juliette.kennedy@helsinki.fi>

Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative.
The Encyclopedia Now Needs Your Support
Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free