Empathy
The concept of empathy is used to refer to a wide range of psychological capacities that are thought of as being central for constituting humans as social creatures, allowing us to know what other people are thinking and feeling, to emotionally engage with them, to share their thoughts and feelings, and to care for their well–being. Ever since the eighteenth century, due particularly to the influence of the writings of David Hume and Adam Smith, those capacities have been at the center of scholarly investigations into the underlying psychological basis of our social and moral nature. Yet, the concept of empathy is of relatively recent intellectual heritage. Moreover, since researchers in different disciplines have focused their investigations on very specific aspects of the broad range of empathy-related phenomena, one should probably not be surprised by a certain amount of conceptual confusion and a multiplicity of definitions associated with the empathy concept in a number of different scientific and non-scientific discourses. The purpose of this entry is to clarify the empathy concept by surveying its history in various philosophical and psychological discussions and by indicating why empathy was and should be regarded to be of such central importance in understanding human agency in ordinary contexts, in the human sciences, and for the constitution of ourselves as social and moral agents. More specifically, a short historical introduction will articulate the philosophical context within which the empathy concept was coined, before we elaborate on how to distinguish conceptually between the various empathy-related phenomena (sections 1 & 2). Section 3 will address the contention that empathy is the primary epistemic means for knowing other minds, the unique method distinguishing the human from the natural sciences, and discuss possible limitations in our ability to empathically make sense or grasp the experiential or phenomenal perspective of others. The last or fourth section will then focus on claims that view empathy as the fundamental social glue and that understand empathy as the main psychological mechanism enabling us to establish and maintain social relations, and take an evaluative stance towards each other.
- 1. Historical Introduction
- 2. Aspects of Empathy-Related Phenomena and Their Conceptual Differentiations
- 3. Empathy and Knowledge of Other Minds
- 3.1 Empathy and the Traditional Problem of Other Minds
- 3.2 Mirror Neurons, Simulation, and the Discussion of Empathy in the Contemporary Theory of Mind Debate
- 3.3 Empathy as the Unique Method of the Human Sciences
- 3.4 The Structural Limits of Empathy or How to Make Sense of Another Person’s Perspective and Experiences?
- 4. Empathy, Moral Philosophy, and Moral Psychology
- Bibliography
- Academic Tools
- Other Internet Resources
- Related Entries
1. Historical Introduction
Before the psychologist Edward Titchener (1867–1927) introduced the term “empathy” in 1909 into the English language as the translation of the German term “Einfühlung” (or “feeling into”), “sympathy” was the term commonly used to refer to empathy-related phenomena. If one were to point to a conceptual core for understanding these phenomena, it is probably best to point to David Hume’s dictum that “the minds of men are mirrors to one another,”(Hume 1739–40 [1978], 365) since in encountering other persons, humans can resonate with and recreate that person’s thoughts and emotions on different dimensions of cognitive complexity. While, as we will see, not everybody shares such a resonance conception of empathy(some philosophers in the phenomenological tradition emphatically reject it), it certainly constitutes the center of Theodor Lipps’s understanding, who Titchener had in mind in his translation of “Einfühlung” as “empathy.”
Theodor Lipps (1851–1914)was also very familiar with the work of David Hume (see the introduction to Coplan and Goldie 2011 in this respect). More importantly, it was Theodor Lipps, whose work transformed empathy/Einfühlung from a concept of nineteenth-century German aesthetics into a central category of the philosophy of the social and human sciences. To understand this transformation, we first need to appreciate the reasons why philosophers of the nineteenth century thought it necessary to appeal to empathy in order to account for our ability to appreciate natural objects and artefacts in an aesthetic manner. According to the dominant (even though not universally accepted) positivistic and empiricist conception, sense data constitute the fundamental basis for our investigation of the world. Yet from a phenomenological perspective, our perceptual encounter with aesthetic objects and our appreciation of them as being beautiful—our admiration of a beautiful sunset, for example—seems to be as direct as our perception of an object as being red or square. By appealing to the psychological mechanisms of empathy, philosophers intended to provide an explanatory account of the phenomenological immediacy of our aesthetic appreciation of objects. More specifically, for Lipps, our empathic encounter with external objects triggers inner “processes” that give rise to experiences similar to ones that I have when I engage in various activities involving the movement of my body. Since my attention is perceptually focused on the external object, I experience it—or I automatically project my experiences—as being in the object. If those experiences are in some way apprehended in a positive manner and as being in some sense life-affirming, I perceive the object as beautiful; otherwise, as ugly. In the first case, Lipps speaks of positive; in the latter of negative empathy. Lipps also characterizes our experience of beauty as “objectified self-enjoyment,” since we are impressed by the “vitality” and “life potentiality” that lies in the perceived object (Lipps 1906, 1903a,b. For the contemporary discussion of empathy’s role in aesthetics, see particularly Breithaupt 2009; Coplan and Goldie 2011 (Part II); Curtis & Koch 2009; and Keen 2007. For a recent history of the empathy concept, see also Lanzoni 2018).
In his Aesthetik, Lipps closely links our aesthetic perception and our perception of another embodied person as a minded creature. The nature of aesthetic empathy is always the “experience of another human” (1905, 49). We appreciate another object as beautiful because empathy allows us to see it in analogy to another human body. Similarly, we recognize another organism as a minded creature because of empathy. Empathy in this context is more specifically understood as a phenomenon of “inner imitation,” where my mind mirrors the mental activities or experiences of another person based on the observation of their bodily activities or facial expressions. Empathy is ultimately based on an innate disposition for motor mimicry, a fact that is well established in the psychological literature and was already noticed by Adam Smith (1853). Even though such a disposition is not always externally manifested, Lipps suggests that it is always present as an inner tendency giving rise to similar kinaesthetic sensations in the observer as felt by the observed target. In seeing the angry face of another person, we instinctually have a tendency to imitate it and “imitate” her anger in this manner. Since we are not aware of such tendencies, we see the anger in her face (Lipps 1907). Although Lipps’s primary examples of empathy focus on the recognition of emotions expressed in bodily gestures or facial expressions, his conception of empathy should not be understood as being limited to such cases. As his remarks about intellectual empathy suggest (1903b/05), he regards our recognition of all mental activities—insofar as they are activities requiring human effort—as being based on empathy or on inner imitation.
2. Aspects of Empathy-Related Phenomena and Their Conceptual Differentiations
In addition, the contemporary concept of empathy and current empathy research can be understood as the merger of two distinct strands of philosophical and psychological research traditions within which the investigation of our empathic capacities played a major role. Starting in the nineteenth century, empathy was discussed as the central means of knowing other minds, answering questions about the causal psychological mechanisms underlying our ability to know what others are thinking and feeling, or questions about how we can epistemically justify our psychological understanding of other people. For twentieth-century psychologists, that meant that one defined empathy primarily in cognitive terms as, for instance, “the intellectual or imaginative apprehension of another’s condition or state of mind,” to use Hogan’s (1969) terminology. Within this area of psychological research, one is primarily interested in determining the reliability and accuracy of our ability to perceive and recognize other persons’ enduring personality traits, attitudes, and values, and occurrent mental states. One also investigates the various factors that influence empathic accuracy. One has, for example, been interested in determining whether empathic ability depends on gender, age, family background, intelligence, emotional stability, the nature of interpersonal relations, or whether it depends on specific motivations of the observer. (For a survey, see Ickes 1993 and 2003; and Taft 1955). A more detailed account of the research on empathic accuracy and some of its earlier methodological difficulties can be found in the
Supplementary Document: The Study of Cognitive Empathy and Empathic Accuracy.
Harking back to eighteenth-century moral philosophy, particularly David Hume and Adam Smith (See also Wispe 1991), psychologists also investigated empathy’s role in constituting us as social and moral creatures who emotionally connect to other humans and care for their well-being. Within this context, one primarily conceives of empathy as an affective phenomenon having to do with human emotions since emotions, rather than cognitive states, are generally regarded to be intimately tied to human motivations. Anyone reading the psychological empathy literature has to be struck by the fact that empathy tended at times to be incredibly broadly defined. Stotland, for instance, one of the earliest researchers who understood empathy exclusively as an emotional phenomenon, defined it as “an observer’s reacting emotionally because he perceives that another is experiencing or is about to experience an emotion” (1969, 272). According to Stotland’s definition, very diverse emotional responses such as feeling envy, feeling annoyed, feeling distressed, being relieved about, feeling pity, or feeling what Germans call Schadenfreude (feeling joyful about the misfortune of another) have all to be counted as empathic reactions. Since the 1980’s however, psychologists have fine-tuned their understanding of empathy conceptually; thereby implicitly acknowledging the conceptual distinctions articulated by Max Scheler (1973) almost a century earlier. (See also the survey in the Introduction to Eisenberg/Strayer 1987 and Batson 2009). One nowadays tends to distinguish broadly between four different empathy-related phenomena: emotional contagion, empathy proper, sympathy, and personal distress.
-
Emotional contagion: Emotional contagion is a resonance phenomenon of a relatively basic form. It occurs when people start feeling similar emotions caused merely by the association with other people. You start feeling joyful because other people around you are joyful, or you start feeling panicky because you are in a crowd of people feeling panicked. Emotional contagion, however, does not require that one is aware of the fact that one experiences the emotions because other people experience them; rather, one experiences them primarily as one’s own emotion (Scheler 1973, 22). A newborn infant’s reactive cry to the distress cry of another, which Hoffman takes as a “rudimentary precursor of empathic distress” (Hoffman 2000, 65), can probably be understood as a phenomenon of emotional contagion, since the infant is not able to properly distinguish between self and other.
-
Proper Empathy: In contrast to mere emotional contagion, genuine empathy presupposes the ability to differentiate between oneself and the other and an awareness that one is resonating with or reenacting the thoughts and feelings of the other person. It requires, for instance, that one is minimally aware of the fact that one is having an emotional experience due to the perception of the other’s emotion, or more generally, due to attending to his situation. In seeing a sad face of another and feeling sad oneself, such a feeling of sadness should count as genuinely empathic only if one recognizes that in feeling sad, one’s attention is still focused on the other and that it is not an appropriate reaction to aspects of one’s own life. Researchers, however, differ in whether they understand such empathy in a narrow or broader manner. More narrowly understood, empathy is conceived of in an affective sense only as the vicarious sharing of an affect. Authors can differ in how strictly they interpret the phrase of vicariously sharing an affect. For some, it requires that the empathizers and the persons they empathize with need to be in very similar affective states (Coplan 2011; de Vignemont and Singer 2006; Jacob 2011). For Hoffman, on the other hand, it is an emotional response requiring only “the involvement of psychological processes that make a person have feelings that are more congruent with another’s situation than with his own situation” (Hoffman 2000, 30). According to this definition, empathy does not necessarily require that the subject and target feel similar emotions (even though this is most often the case). Rather, the definition also includes cases of feeling sad when seeing a child who plays joyfully but who does not know that it has been diagnosed with a serious illness (assuming that this is how the other person himself or herself would feel if he or she fully understood his or her situation). Outside the realm of a direct perceptual encounter, such empathy also involves some appreciation of the other person’s emotion as an appropriate response to his or her situation. To be happy or unhappy because one’s child is happy or sad should not necessarily count as an empathic emotion. It cannot count as a vicarious emotional response if it is due to the perception of the outside world from the perspective of the observer, and our desire that our children should be happy. Our happiness about the happiness of our children is not an emotional state that is more congruent with their situation. Rather, it is an emotional response appropriate to my own perspective on the world. In order for my happiness or unhappiness to be genuinely empathic, it has to be happiness or unhappiness about what makes the other person happy. Accordingly, if I share another person’s emotion vicariously, I do not merely have to be in an affective state with a similar phenomenal quality. Rather, my affective state has to be directed toward the same intentional object. (See Sober and Wilson 1998, 231–237 and Maibom 2007. For a critical discussion of how and whether such vicarious sharing is possible, see also Deonna 2007 and Matravers 2018). Yet not all authors conceive of proper empathy merely as an affective phenomenon. Particularly within the context of investigating how we know other minds (see Goldman 2011 and Stueber 2006), empathy is more comprehensively conceived of as including not only affective states but all states that constitute a person’s perspective, their emotions, value commitments, desires, but also their cognitive states, such as their beliefs. Already, Adam Smith (1853) constitutes a good example of such a broad understanding of proper empathy. Finally, others suggest that it is best to distinguish between affective sharing and perspective taking (Decety and Cowell 2015). Notice that a broad understanding of empathy (as including both cognitive and affective states) is not equivalent to a merely cognitive conception of empathy that one also encounters at times in the literature. Indeed, one might wonder whether the term ‘cognitive empathy’ is in some sense a misleading one, since it often seems to refer to our general ability to know or infer the mental states of others, regardless of how we arrive at such knowledge. Merely knowing or inferring that somebody is feeling sad, because she was diagnosed with depression based on one’s knowledge of the nature of depression, would count as a case of cognitive empathy (See Spaulding 2017 for a discussion of cognitive empathy). Yet empathy tends to be associated with knowing somehow from the inside of how a person feels or thinks, which seems to require some sort of resonance or taking the perspective of the person we are concerned with (For a comprehensive anthology about empathy, see also Maibom 2017).
-
Sympathy: In contrast to empathy, sympathy—or what some authors also refer to as empathic concern—is not an emotion that is congruent with the other’s emotion or situation, such as feeling the sadness of the other person’s grieving for the death of his father. Rather, sympathy is seen as an emotion sui generis that has the other’s negative emotion or situation as its object from the perspective of somebody who cares for the other person’s well-being (Darwall 1998). In this sense, sympathy consists of “feeling sorrow or concern for the distressed or needy other,” a feeling for the other out of a “heightened awareness of the suffering of another person as something that needs to be alleviated.” (Eisenberg 2000a, 678; Wispe 1986, 318; and Wispe 1991). What we call compassion should also be understood as a form of sympathy, a form of sympathy that is about major calamities that befall another person. While we can sympathize with another person’s pain due to a paper cut, we would not call such feelings examples of compassion (See Blum 1980, Snow 1991, Nussbaum 2001, part II). Whereas it is quite plausible to assume that empathy—that is, empathy with negative emotions of another or what Hoffman (2000) calls “veridical empathic distress”—under certain conditions (and when certain developmental markers are achieved) can give rise to sympathy, it should be stressed that the relation between affective empathy and sympathy is a contingent one; the understanding of which requires further empirical research. First, sympathy does not necessarily require feeling any kind of congruent emotions on the part of the observer; a detached recognition or representation that the other is in need or suffers might be sufficient. (See Scheler 1973 and Nichols 2004). Second, empathy or empathic distress might not at all lead to sympathy. People in the helping professions, who are so accustomed to the misery of others, suffer at times from compassion fatigue. It is also possible to experience empathic overarousal because one is emotionally so overwhelmed by one’s empathic feelings that one is unable to be concerned with the suffering of the other (Hoffman 2000, chap. 8). In the later case, one’s empathic feeling are transformed or give rise to mere personal distress, a reactive emotional phenomenon that needs to be distinguished from emotional contagion, empathy, and sympathy.
-
Personal Distress: Personal distress in the context of empathy research is understood as a reactive emotion in response to the perception/recognition of another’s negative emotion or situation. Yet, while personal distress is other-caused like sympathy, it is, in contrast to sympathy, primarily self-oriented. In this case, another person’s distress does not make me feel bad for him or her, it just makes me feel bad, or “alarmed, grieved, upset, worried, disturbed, perturbed, distressed, and troubled;” to use the list of adjectives that according to Batson’s research indicates personal distress (Batson et al. 1987 and Batson 1991). And, in contrast to empathic emotions as defined above, my personal distress is not any more congruent with the emotion or situation of another. Rather, it wholly defines my own outlook on the world.
While it is conceptually necessary to differentiate between these various emotional responses, it has to be admitted that it is empirically not very easy to discriminate between them, since they tend to occur together. Think or imagine yourself attending the funeral of the child of a friend or good acquaintance. You probably are “infected” by the sadness of people around you, you imagine how close relatives of the deceased feel, you sympathize with their loss, but you also might be distressed about having to attend such a sad affair, since you have very important things to attend to in your personal life. This is probably one reason why early researchers tended not to distinguish between the above aspects in their study of empathy-related phenomena. Yet since the above distinctions refer to very different psychological mechanisms, it is central to distinguish between them when empirically assessing the impact and contribution of empathy to an agent’s pro-social motivation and behavior. Given the ambiguity of the empathy concept within psychology—particularly in the earlier literature—in evaluating and comparing different empirical empathy studies, it is always crucial to keep in mind how empathy has been defined. Equally important in evaluating empirical studies, one has to pay attention to how such abstractly defined concepts are operationalized within these studies. For a more extensive discussion of the methods used by psychologists to measure empathy, see the Supplementary document on Measuring Empathy.
Notice that when we are exploring empathy in the next sections as an epistemic means for knowing other minds (section 3) and as the basis for human sociality and morality (section 4), we will be conceiving of it as what we have called proper empathy above, that is, as requiring a self-other differentiation.
3. Empathy and Knowledge of Other Minds
3.1 Empathy and the Traditional Problem of Other Minds
It was indeed Lipps’s claim that empathy should be understood as the primary epistemic means for gaining knowledge of other minds that was the focus of a lively debate among philosophers at the beginning of the 20th century (Prandtl 1910, Stein 1917, Scheler 1973). Even philosophers, who did not agree with Lipps’s specific explication, found the concept of empathy appealing because his argument for his position was closely tied to a thorough critique of what was widely seen at that time as the only alternative for conceiving of knowledge of other minds, that is, Mill’s inference from analogy. Traditionally, the inference from analogy presupposes a Cartesian conception of the mind according to which access to our own mind is direct and infallible, whereas knowledge of other minds is inferential, fallible, and based on evidence about other persons’ observed physical behavior. More formally, one can characterize the inference from analogy as consisting of the following premises or steps.
- Another person X manifests behavior of type B.
- In my own case behavior of type B is caused by mental state of type M.
- Since my and X’s outward behavior of type B is similar, it has to have similar inner mental causes. (It is thus assumed that I and the other persons are psychologically similar in the relevant sense.)
- Therefore, the other person’s behavior (X’s behavior) is caused by a mental state of type M.
Like Wittgenstein, but predating him considerably, Lipps argues in his 1907 article “Das Wissen von fremden Ichen” that the inference from analogy falls fundamentally short of solving the philosophical problem of other minds. Lipps does not argue against the inference from analogy because of its evidentially slim basis, but because it does not allow us to understand its basic presupposition that another person has a mind that is psychologically similar to our own mind. The inference from analogy thus cannot be understood as providing us with evidence for the claim that the other person has mental states like we do because, within its Cartesian framework, we are unable to conceive of other minds in the first place. For Lipps, analogical reasoning requires the contradictory undertaking of inferring another person’s anger and sadness based on my sadness and anger, yet to think of that sadness and anger simultaneously as something “absolutely different” from my anger and sadness. More generally, analogical inference is a contradictory undertaking because it entails “entertaining a completely new thought about an I, that however is not me, but something absolutely different” (Lipps 1907, 708, my translation).
Yet while Lipps diagnoses the problem of the inference of analogy within the context of a Cartesian conception of the mind quite succinctly, he fails to explain how empathy is able to provide us with an epistemically sanctioned understanding of other minds or why our “feeling into” the other person’s mind is more than a mere projection. More importantly, Lipps does not sufficiently explain why empathy does not encounter similar problems to the ones diagnosed for the inference from analogy and how empathy allows us to conceive of other persons as having a mind similar to our own if we are directly acquainted only with our own mental states. Wittgenstein’s critique of the inference from analogy is, in the end, more penetrating because he recognizes that its problem depends on a Cartesian account of mental concepts. If my grasp of a mental concept is exclusively constituted by me experiencing something in a certain way, then it is impossible for me to conceive of how that very same concept can be applied to somebody else, given that I cannot experience somebody else’s mental states. I therefore cannot conceive of how another person can be in the same mental state as I am because that would require that I can conceive of my mental state as something, which I do not experience. But according to the Cartesian conception, this seems to be a conceptually impossible task. Moreover, if one holds on to a Cartesian conception of the mind, it is not clear how appealing to empathy, as conceived of by Lipps, should help us in conceiving of mental states as belonging to another mind.
Within the phenomenological tradition, the above shortcomings of Lipps’s position of empathy were quite apparent (see, for example, Stein 1917, 24 and Scheler 1973, 236). Yet despite the fact that they did not accept Lipps’s explication of empathy as being based on mechanisms of inner resonance and projection, authors within the phenomenological tradition of philosophy were persuaded by Lipps’s critique of the inference from analogy. For that very reason, Husserl and Stein, for example, continued using the concept of empathy and regarded empathy as an irreducible “type of experiential act sui generis” (Stein 1917, 10), which allows us to view another person as being analogous to ourselves without this “analogizing apprehension” constituting an inference of analogy (Husserl 1931 [1963], 141). Scheler probably went the furthest in rejecting the Cartesian framework in thinking about the apprehension of other minds, while remaining committed to something like the concept of empathy.[1] (In order to contrast his position from Lipps, Scheler preferred to use the term “nachfühlen” rather than “einfühlen.”) For Scheler, the fundamental mistake of the debate about the apprehension of other minds consists in the fact that it does not take seriously certain phenomenological facts. Prima facie, we do not encounter merely the bodily movements of another person. Rather, we are directly recognizing specific mental states because they are characteristically expressed in states of the human body; in facial expressions, in gestures, in the tone of voice, and so on. Empathy within the phenomenological tradition then is not conceived of as a resonance phenomenon requiring the observer to recreate the mental states of the other person in his or her own mind but as a special perceptual act (See Scheler 1973, particularly 232–258; For a succinct explication of the debate about empathy in the phenomenological tradition consult Zahavi 2010)
3.2 Mirror Neurons, Simulation, and the Discussion of Empathy in the Contemporary Theory of Mind Debate
The idea that empathy understood as inner imitation is the primary epistemic means for understanding other minds has however been revived in the 1980’s by simulation theorists in the context of the interdisciplinary debate about folk psychology; an empirically informed debate about how best to describe the underlying causal mechanisms of our folk psychological abilities to interpret, explain, and predict other agents. (See Davies and Stone 1995, see Lavelle 2019 for a more recent summary). In contrast to theory theory, simulation theorists conceive of our ordinary mindreading abilities as an ego-centric method and as a “knowledge–poor” strategy, where I do not utilize a folk psychological theory but use myself as a model for the other person’s mental life. It is not the place here to discuss the contemporary debate extensively, but it has to be emphasized that contemporary simulation theorists vigorously discuss how to account for our grasp of mental concepts and whether simulation theory is committed to Cartesianism. Whereas Goldman (2002, 2006) links his version of simulation theory to a neo-Cartesian account of mental concepts, other simulation theorists develop versions of simulation theory that are not committed to a Cartesian conception of the mind. (Gordon 1995a, b, and 2000; Heal 2003; and Stueber 2012a).
Moreover, neuroscientific findings according to which so-called mirror neurons play an important role in recognizing another person’s emotional states and in understanding the goal-directedness of his behavior have been understood as providing empirical evidence for Lipps’ idea of empathy as inner imitation. With the help of the term “mirror neuron,” scientists refer to the fact that there is significant overlap between neural areas of excitation that underlie our observation of another person’s action and areas that are stimulated when we execute the very same action. A similar overlap between neural areas of excitation has also been established for our recognition of another person’s emotion based on his facial expression and our experiencing the emotion. (For a survey on mirror neurons, see Gallese 2003a and b, Goldman 2006, chap. 6; Keysers 2011; Rizzolatti and Craighero 2004; and particularly Rizzolatti and Sinigaglia 2008). Since the face-to-face encounter between persons is the primary situation within which human beings recognize themselves as minded creatures and attribute mental states to others, the system of mirror neurons has been interpreted as playing a causally central role in establishing intersubjective relations between minded creatures. For that very reason, the neuroscientist Gallese thinks of mirror neurons as constituting what he calls the “shared manifold of intersubjectivity” (Gallese 2001, 44). Stueber (2006, chap. 4)—inspired by Lipps’s conception of empathy as inner imitation—refers to mirror neurons as mechanisms of basic empathy;[2] as mechanisms that allow us to apprehend directly another person’s emotions in light of his facial expressions and that enable us to understand his bodily movements as goal-directed actions, that is, as being directed towards an external object like a person reaching for the cup (Goldman 2011 speaks in this context about mirroring empathy). The evidence from mirror neurons—and the fact that in perceiving other people we use very different neurobiological mechanisms than in the perception of physical objects—does suggest that in our primary perceptual encounter with the world, we do not merely encounter physical objects. Rather, even on this basic level, we distinguish already between mere physical objects and objects that are more like us (See also Meltzoff and Brooks 2001). The mechanisms of basic empathy have to be seen as Nature’s way of dissolving one of the principal assumptions of the traditional philosophical discussion about other minds shared by opposing positions such as Cartesianism and Behaviorism; that is, that we perceive other people primarily as physical objects and do not distinguish already on the perceptual level between physical objects like trees and minded creatures like ourselves. Mechanisms of basic empathy might therefore be interpreted as providing us with a perceptual and non-conceptual basis for developing an intersubjectively accessible folk psychological framework that applies to the subject and observed other (Stueber 2006, 142–45).
It needs to be acknowledged that this interpretation of mirror neurons crucially depends on the assumption that the primary function of mirror neurons consists in providing us with a cognitive grasp of another person’s actions and emotions. This interpretation has been criticized by researchers and philosophers who think that neural resonance presupposes rather than provides us with an understanding of what is going on in the minds of others (Csibra 2007, Hickok 2008, and 2014). They have also pointed out that in observing another person’s emotion or behavior, we never fully “mirror” another person’s neural stimulation. The neuroscientist Jean Decety has argued that in observing another person’s pain, our vicariously stimulated pain matrix is not sensitive to the phenomenal quality of pain. Rather, it is sensitive to pain as an indicator of “aversion and withdrawal when exposed to danger and threats”(Decety and Cowell 2015, 6 and Decety 2010). At least as far as empathy for pain is concerned, our neural resonance is also modulated by a variety of contextual factors, such as how close we feel to the observed subject, whether we regard the pain to be morally justified (as in the case of punishment, for example) or whether we regard it as unavoidable and necessary, such as in a medical procedure (Singer and Lamm 2009; but see also Allen 2010, Borg 2007, Debes 2010, Gallese 2016, Goldman 2009, Iacoboni 2011, Jacob 2008, Rizzolatti and Sinigaglia 2016).
Yet it should be noted that everyday mindreading is not restricted to the realm of basic empathy. Ordinarily, we not only recognize that other persons are afraid or that they are reaching for a particular object. We understand their behavior in more complex social contexts in terms of their reasons for acting using the full range of psychological concepts, including the concepts of belief and desire. Evidence from neuroscience shows that these mentalizing tasks involve very different neuronal areas, such as the medial prefrontal cortex, the temporoparietal cortex, and the cingulate cortex. (For a survey, see Kain and Perner 2003; Frith and Frith 2003; Zaki and Ochsner 2012). Low-level mindreading in the realm of basic empathy has therefore to be distinguished from higher levels of mindreading (Goldman 2006). It is clear that low-level forms of understanding other persons have to be conceived of as being relatively knowledge-poor, as they do not involve a psychological theory or complex psychological concepts. How exactly one should conceive of high level mindreading abilities, whether they involve primarily knowledge–poor simulation strategies or knowledge–rich inferences is controversially debated within the contemporary debate about our folk psychological mindreading abilities(See Davies and Stone 1995, Gopnik and Meltzoff 1997, Gordon 1995, Currie and Ravenscroft 2002, Heal 2003, Nichols and Stich 2003, and Goldman 2006). Simulation theorists, however, insist that even more complex forms of understanding other agents involve resonance phenomena that engage our cognitively intricate capacities of imaginatively adopting the perspective of another person and reenacting or recreating their thought processes and their reasons for acting (For various forms of perspective-taking, see Coplan 2011 and Goldie 2000). Accordingly, simulation theorists distinguish between different types of empathy, such as between basic and reenactive empathy (Stueber 2006) or between mirroring and reconstructive empathy (Goldman 2011). Interestingly, the debate about how to conceive of these more complex forms of mindreading resonates with the traditional debate about whether empathy is the unique method of the human sciences and whether or not one has to strictly distinguish between the methods of the human and the natural sciences. Equally noteworthy is the fact that in the contemporary theory of mind debate, voices have grown louder that assert that the contemporary theory of mind debate fundamentally misconceives the nature of social cognition. In light of insights from the phenomenological and hermeneutic traditions in philosophy, they claim that on the most basic level, empathy should not be conceived of as a resonance phenomenon but as a type of direct perception. (See particularly Zahavi 2010; Zahavi and Overgaard 2012, but Jacob 2011 for a response). More complex forms of social cognition are also not to be understood as being based on either theory or empathy/simulation, rather they are better best conceived of as the ability to directly fit observed units of actions into larger narrative or cultural frameworks (For this debate see Gallagher 2012, Gallagher and Hutto 2008, Hutto 2008, Seemann 2011, Stueber 2011, and various articles in Matravers and Waldow 2018. For a pluralistic conception of mindreading see also Fiebich et. 2017 and Spaulding 2017). Regardless of how one views this specific debate, it should be clear that ideas about mindreading developed originally by proponents of empathy at the beginning of the 20th century can no longer be easily dismissed and have to be taken seriously.
3.3 Empathy as the Unique Method of the Human Sciences
At the beginning of the 20th century, empathy understood as a non-inferential and non-theoretical method of grasping the content of other minds became closely associated with the concept of understanding (Verstehen); a concept that was championed by the hermeneutic tradition of philosophy concerned with explicating the methods used in grasping the meaning and significance of texts, works of arts, and actions (For a survey of this tradition, see Grondin 1994). Notice, however, that in contrast to the contemporary debate about folk psychology, the debate about empathy in the philosophy of social science is not concerned with investigating underlying causal mechanisms. Rather, it addresses normative questions of how to justify a particular explanation or interpretation. For those reasons, hermeneutic thinkers insisted that the method used in understanding the significance of a text or a historical event has to be fundamentally distinguished from the method used in explaining an event within the context of the natural sciences. This methodological dualism is famously expressed by Droysen in saying that “historical research does not want to explain; that is, derive in a form of an inferential argument, rather it wants to understand” (Droysen 1977, 403), and similarly in Dilthey’s dictum that “we explain nature, but understand the life of the soul” (Dilthey 1961, vol. 5, 144). To be fair to Droysen and other nineteenth-century hermeneutic authors, such as Schleiermacher (1998), it has to be acknowledged that they never conceived of understanding as being solely based on an act of imaginatively “transporting” oneself in the perspective of another. These “psychological interpretations” were always to be accompanied by other interpretive methods to ascertain the reliability of historical sources or investigate the linguistic norms of a particular time (for a more recent evaluation of these claims, see the various articles in Feest 2012). Nevertheless, the close association of the concepts of empathy and understanding and the associated claim that empathy is the sole and unique method of the human sciences also facilitated the decline of the empathy concept and its almost utter disregard by philosophers of the human and social sciences later on, in both the analytic and continental/hermeneutic traditions of philosophy. As a result, most philosophers of the human and social sciences maintained their distance from the idea that empathy is central for our understanding of other minds and mental phenomena. Notable exceptions in this respect are R.G. Collingwood and his followers, who suggested that reenacting another person’s thoughts is necessary for understanding them as rational agents (Collingwood 1946, Dray 1957 and 1995).
Philosophers arguing for a hermeneutic conception of the human and social sciences still insist on a strict methodological division between the human and the natural sciences.[3] Yet they nowadays favor the concept of understanding (Verstehen) and reject the earlier identification of understanding and empathy for two specific reasons. First, empathy is no longer seen as the unique method of the human sciences because facts of significance, which a historian or an interpreter of literary and non-literary texts is interested in, do not solely depend on facts within the individual mind. A historian, for example, is not bound by the agent’s perspective in telling the story of a particular historical period (Danto 1965). Similarly, philosophers such as Hans Georg Gadamer have argued that the significance of a text is not tied to the author’s intentions in writing the text. In reading a text by Shakespeare or Plato, we are not primarily interested in finding out what Plato or Shakespeare said, but what these texts themselves say. (Gadamer 1989; for a critical discussion, see Skinner (in Tully 1988); “Introduction” in Kögler and Stueber 2000).
The above considerations, however, do not justify the claim that empathy has no role to play within the context of the human sciences. It justifies merely the claim that empathy cannot be their only method, at least as long as one admits that recognizing the thoughts of individual agents has to play some role in the interpretive project of the human sciences. Yet hermeneutic thinkers also assert that conceiving of empathy as the sole method for understanding individual agents is epistemically naive. Individual agents are always socially and culturally embedded creatures. Understanding other agents thus presupposes an understanding of the cultural context within which an agent functions. If this cultural background is very different, interpreters can not very easily put themselves in the shoes of the other person. If understanding medieval knights, to use an example of Winch (1958), requires us to think exactly as the medieval knight did, then it is not clear how such a task can be accomplished from an interpretive perspective constituted by very different cultural presuppositions. Making sense of other minds has, therefore, to be seen as an activity that is a culturally mediated one; a fact that empathy theorists according to this line of critique do not sufficiently take into account when they conceive of understanding other agents as a direct meeting of minds that is independent of and unaided by information about how these agents are embedded in a broader social environment. Yet rather than showing that empathy and imaginative perspective-taking are not at all involved in understanding other people, these considerations seem to emphasize the need for additional information and point to some difficulties and possible limitations of our ability to empathize with others. Some of them will be discussed in the next subsection. (See also Stueber 2006, ch. 6, Zahavi 2001, 2005; for the later Dilthey see Makreel 2000. For a critical discussion of whether the concept of understanding without recourse to empathy is useful for marking an epistemic distinction between the human and natural sciences, consult also Stueber 2012b. Within the context of anthropology, Hollan and Throop argue that empathy is best understood as a dynamic, culturally situated, temporally extended, and dialogical process actively involving not only the interpreter but also his or her interpretee. See Hollan 20012; Hollan and Throop 2008, 2001; Throop 2010).
Philosophers who reject the methodological dualism between the human and the natural sciences, commonly referred to as naturalists in the philosophy of social science, have an additional reason for rejecting empathy as a serious epistemic method of knowledge acquisition. For them, even the human or social sciences are in the business of providing epistemically justified explanations (and predictions) of observed or recorded events (see also Henderson 1993). As particularly Hempel (1965) has argued, to explain an event involves—at least implicitly—an appeal to law-like regularities providing us with reasons for expecting that an event of a certain kind will occur under specific circumstances. At most, empathy is granted a heuristic role in the context of discovery. It can not play any role within the context of justification. Empathy might allow me to recognize that I would have acted in the same manner as somebody else. Yet it does not epistemically sanction the claim that anybody of a particular type or anybody who is in that type of situation will act in this manner.
Hempel’s argument against empathy has certainly not gone unchallenged. Within the philosophy of history, Dray (1957), following Collingwood, has argued that empathy plays an epistemically irreducible role, since we explain actions in terms of an agent’s reasons. For him, such reason explanations do not appeal to empirical generalizations but to normative principles of actions outlining how a person should act in a particular situation. Similar arguments have been articulated by Jaegwon Kim (1984, 1998). Yet as Stueber (2006, chap. 5) argues, such a response to Hempel would require us to implausibly conceive of reason explanations as being very different from ordinary causal explanations. Moreover, as Hempel himself suggests, appealing to normative principles explains at most why a person should have acted in a certain manner. It does not explain why he ultimately acted in that way. (For Kim’s recent attempt to account for the explanatory character of action explanations by acknowledging the centrality of the first-person perspective, see also Kim 2010). Despite these concessions to Hempel, Stueber suggests that empathy (specifically reenactive empathy) has to be acknowledged as playing a central role even in the context of justification. For him, folk psychological explanations have to be understood as being tied to the domain of rational agency. In contrast to explanations in terms of mere inner causes, folk psychological explanations retain their explanatory force only as long as agents’ beliefs and desires can also be understood as reasons for their actions. The epistemic justification of such folk psychological explanations implicitly relies on generalizations involving folk psychological notions such as belief and desire. Yet the existence of such generalizations alone does not establish specific beliefs and desires as reasons for a person’s actions. Elaborating on considerations by Heal (2003) and Collingwood (1946), Stueber suggests that recognizing beliefs and desires as reasons requires the interpreter to be sensitive to an agent’s other relevant beliefs and desires. Individual thoughts function as reasons for rational agency only relative to a specific framework of an agent’s thoughts that are relevant for consideration in a specific situation. Most plausibly—given our persistent inability to solve the frame problem—recognizing which of another agent’s thoughts are relevant in specific contexts requires the practical ability of reenacting another person’s thoughts in one’s own mind. Empathy’s central epistemic role has to be admitted, since beliefs and desires can be understood only in this manner as an agent’s reasons (See Stueber 2008. For a related discussion about the role of understanding in contemporary epistemology and philosophy of science, see Grimm 2016 and Grimm, Baumberger, and Ammon 2017).
3.4 The Structural Limits of Empathy or How to Make Sense of Another Person’s Perspective and Experiences?
The debate about the epistemic scope of our empathic capacities has been revived within the contemporary interdisciplinary context involving mainly the psychological sciences, philosophy, and at times, political science. To a large extent, this debate has been driven by empirical research investigating the biases that tend to limit the scope of our empathic engagement with others due to a variety of social power differentials, perceptions of similarities between the interpreter and interpretee, and differences in class, race, gender, or ethnicity. Without doubt, these debates are of utmost importance, and so is the debate about how to mitigate the influence of such biases. We will discuss them in the next section when we analyze certain arguments for the morally dark sides of empathy. In some sense, one could also regard such biases to be impacting our motivation to use our empathic imagination to understand others rather than being features that have to do with the structure or nature of empathic perspective-taking (See Spaulding 2024). Moreover, the social biases commonly mentioned do not merely influence empathy, but, more generally, influence and distort all our attitudes and emotional engagement with others. We tend to be more angry and less forgiving, for example, with transgressions of rules committed by people who are perceived to be socially marginalized or part of the social outgroup. In this section, we will, therefore, be discussing epistemic limitations that can be understood as arising from the fact that empathy, at least in its more cognitive advanced form that involves perspective-taking, is the attempt to understand the subjectivity of another person’s perspective with the help of our own idiosyncratic experiences and subjective perspective on the world. Even though each of us has our social biases and tends not to perceive all humans as being on equal footing, we can all be distinguished in light of our unique life experiences. We might also belong to very different cultural and social groups and differ greatly in our value commitments and what we regard as important to really care about. Do such differences ultimately not limit and affect the ability to imaginatively adopt the perspective of a person from a very different social and cultural background? Can we be epistemically confident, for instance, that a person from a scientific culture can fully adopt the perspective of a person from a more traditional religious and ritualistic culture, a topic that has been intensely debated in the so-called rationality wars in anthropology in the 1970s?
The investigation into the epistemic limitations of empathy also gained new urgency in light of the scientific and philosophical interest in phenomenal consciousness during the last few decades. As it is well known, Nagel (1974) claims that humans can’t imagine what it is like to be a bat because humans lack the physical machinery to realize a bat’s experiences. Even more pertinent to the discussion of empathy’s epistemic scope is Jackson’s thought experiment about Mary the neuroscientist, who lacks knowledge about what it feels like to see something red, because she grew up in a black and white room (Jackson 1982). Mary thus seems to be unable to empathize with another person’s experience of seeing something red that would provide her with knowledge or phenomenal understanding of the other person’s mind from the inside, supposedly a central epistemic function of empathy (Goldie 2000, Heal 2003, Smith 2017). Phenomenal states, at least if you look at them in isolation, appear to differ in this respect from merely propositional or cognitive states. Taking on a pretend belief in the imagination (such as believing that the earth is flat) is a rather easy feat to accomplish, even if we never believed it before. Boisserie-Lacroix and Inchingolo (2021) distinguish for that very reason between agential empathy, reenacting another person’s propositional states, from experiential empathy, allowing us to gain access to the phenomenal side of another person’s inner life. Given our intuition about Mary, imagining another person’s experience would have to depend on our own prior experiences. Only if we have had specific experiences do we seem able to imagine and empathize with what it feels like for another person to see something red, to taste something sweet, to feel sad, to be afraid, or even to fall in love. Yet what if this is not the case? If we are blind or deaf, or if we have grown up in a black and white world like Mary, then our empathic recreation of what another person experiences will fall short of adequately representing what the other person feels. At most, we could know in a propositional manner that she feels afraid, but might not know what that means on a phenomenal level if we never felt afraid. Luckily, we have all been afraid at times. Yet it seems that we never should be able to fully understand what it feels like to be a parent or to be a soldier at war if we never were parents or soldiers at war. Laurie Paul (2014 & 2020) has taken such skepticism to its extreme in recent times by arguing that we could never rationally decide whether we should become parents as we are as non-parents cognitively closed to such experiences (see also Clavel Vazquez and Clavel Vazquez 2023 for a more moderate form of such skepticism based on the insight that all our experiences are essentially embodied ones that are shaped by our individual social and cultural environments).
One can certainly doubt whether empathy with affective phenomenal states can be strictly distinguished from empathy with other attitudes. To use an example from Betzler and Keller (2021) it seems that I only can vicariously feel your outrage about a particular person if I also can reenact your belief that that person was rude to you, and that seems to require that I share at least in the imagination assumptions about what constitutes normatively appropriate ways of behaving (For a debate see also the various articles in Vendrall Ferran and Werner 2025). Regardless of this issue, the question of whether or not empathy is seriously limited deserves an answer. For a more optimistic take on this topic, one can find the following responses in the literature: Most importantly, it needs to be underlined that empathic understanding should never be conceived of as trying to become the other person (See also Maibom 2022). In taking the perspective of another person we are always aware of the fact that we have to adjust our perspective (imaginatively taking on mental states and attitudes that we do not share with the other person and quarantining those attitudes that the other person does not share with us) to approximate the other’s perspective in our own mind (in some sense being always aware of the fact that there are difference between us). These considerations also imply that it is impossible to feel the same way as the person whose feelings I empathically reenact. In vicariously feeling your anger, it is not me who is angry, nor have I become the angry you. Becoming the other through empathic perspective-taking is indeed a conceptual impossibility (Goldie 2011). If that is so, one can also not conceive of becoming the other as a standard according to which we evaluate the epistemic character of empathic understanding. Empathic understanding thus remains bound to the interpreter’s perspective and is always perspectival. A religious person with a Christian background might indeed relate differently to an agent from a Buddhist tradition than a more secular person. This, however, does not mean that we have no way of evaluating the quality of such understanding against each other, since we can also understand each other’s interpretive suggestions and discuss them critically. In regard to interpretations of living agents, those agents also have the option to object to any interpretive renderings of their actions and perspective from the point of view of another. It has, however, to be admitted that the more the other persons differ in their core commitments, attitudes, and what they care about, the more likely it is that we encounter stronger degrees of imaginative resistance. At times, we might even be forced to admit that we can no longer pretend to understand them from the inside and have to fall back on a more theoretical and detached way of explaining their action. Think in this context about the action of school shooters. Being told about any motives they have (based on some confused manifesto they might leave behind) never fully allows us to empathically grasp how their motives can be their reasons for committing these atrocities. All we can point to is that people do act that way at times if they are socially isolated or depressed. Similar considerations have arisen in contemporary research on extremism, particularly violent extremism, where we seem to be compelled to acknowledge the subjectivity of the extremist action while we, at the same time, have great difficulty in empathizing with their perspective. Empathy here seems to lead only to a form of schematic or fragmentary understanding (See in this respect Cassam 2018 & forthcoming, and Stueber forthcoming).
Authors mainly concerned with addressing the question of whether empathy can provide us with knowledge of what it feels like tend to emphasize that we should conceive of empathy as providing us with different degrees of understanding depending on the kind of experiences the empathizer has had and the degree of similarity between the empathizer and the person empathized with. (See Cath 2019, Werner 2023, and Wiltscher 2021). Researchers also point to the role of testimony as providing us with a more direct access to a person’s experiences. (Cath also speaks of a silver standard regarding knowledge of experience in this respect). That is one of the reasons why we try to make sure that we videotape as many of the testimonies of holocaust survivors as possible so that we preserve some access to what it must have felt like for them while being imprisoned in a concentration camp (Berninger 2024). Most importantly, when we discuss phenomenal knowledge in the context of understanding other persons, we tend not to focus on grasping simple qualia that are the focus of philosophers worried about the metaphysical framework of physicalism. We focus on more complex experiences that happen over an extended period. We want to know what it is like to be a parent, or a soldier at war, or how the “goalie’s anxiety at the penalty kick” feels and develops, the topic of one of Peter Handke’s famous novels. To grasp such experiences from the inside does indeed require effort; it requires listening to testimony, and it requires skillfully using one’s imagination through a process of “empathic scaffolding” (Werner 2025, Vendrall Ferran 2025, but also see Kind 2020), adding and subtracting from our repertoire of simpler and complex experiences to approximate the lived experience of the other person. Literature and film might also further help us to improve our imaginative skills (Keen 2007, and a variety of articles in Petraschka and Werner 2024). Of course, these reflections have political implications, since they are centrally relevant for the intense debate about who can and should speak for the marginalized and disadvantaged members of society, given that only the marginalized experience certain injustices firsthand. Similarly, they concern the question of what role empathy has, can, and should play for democratic institutions, democratic deliberation, and whether it can help us to overcome political polarization. Even in these contexts, it tends to be stressed that empathic understanding comes in degrees, and that it requires effort and institutional support in order to be effective. On the other hand, overemphasizing the impossibility of empathic understanding might have detrimental consequences since it suggests that it is impossible to find widespread agreement on the reasons for ameliorating morally unjustifiable aspects of society, undermining in this manner the possibility of solidarity between class, gender, and race boundaries. Indeed, without empathy and institutional support for it, it can be hard to see how deliberation within a democratic society mediating between different perspectives can function. (In this respect, see particularly Hannon 2020 & 2025, Hartmann 2023, Krause 2008 & 2011, Meyers 2017, Mackenzie and Sorial 2021, Morrell 2010, and Read 2021 & 2022).
4. Empathy, Moral Philosophy, and Moral Psychology
Moral philosophers have been less concerned with the epistemic accuracy of gaining knowledge of other minds. They are primarily concerned with articulating and justifying standards according to which we hold each other accountable. Within this context, moral psychology has always played a central role, since one needs to get a clear sense of an agent’s motivational structure in order to explicate the importance of morality for a human life. After all, moral judgments supposedly make demands on an agent’s will and are supposed to provide us with reasons and motivations for acting in a certain manner. Yet moral judgments, at least in the manner in which we conceive of them in modern times, are also regarded as being based on normative standards that, in contrast to mere conventional norms, have universal scope and are valid independent of the features of specific social practices that agents are embedded in. One only needs to think of statements such as “cruelty to innocent children or slavery is morally wrong,” which we view as applying also to social practices where the attitude of its population seems to condone such actions. Moral judgements thus address us from the perspective of the moral stance where we leave behind the perspective of self-love and do not conceive of each other either as friends or foes (see Hume 1987, 75) or as belonging to the in–group or out–group, but where we view each other all to be equal part of a moral community. Finally, and relatedly, in order to view morality as something that is possible for human beings, we also require that our motivations based on or associated with moral reasons have a selfless character. Given to charity for merely selfish reasons, for example, seems to clearly diminish its moral worth and implicitly deny the universal character of a moral demand. Philosophically explicating the importance of morality for human life then has to do the following: It has to explain how it is that we humans do care about morality thusly conceived, it has to address the philosophically even more pertinent question of why it is that we should care about morality or why it is that we should regard judgments issued from the perspective of the moral stance to have normative authority over us; and it has to allow us to understand how it is that we can act self-lessly in a manner that correspond to the demands made on us from the moral stance. Answering all of these questions, however, necessitates at one point explaining how our moral interests are related to our psychological constitution as human beings and how moral demands can be understood as being appropriately addressed to agents who are psychologically structured in that manner.
Prima facie, the difficulty of this enterprise consists in squaring a realistic account of human psychology with the universal scope and intersubjective validity of moral judgments, since human motivation and psychological mechanisms seem to be always situational, local, and of rather limited scope. Moreover, as evolutionary psychologists tell us in–group bias seems to be a universal trait of human psychology. One of the most promising attempts to solve this problem is certainly due to the tradition of eighteenth century moral philosophy associated with the names of David Hume and Adam Smith who tried to address all of the above philosophical desiderata by pointing to the central role that our empathic and sympathetic capacities have for constituting us as social and moral agents and for providing us with the psychological capacities to make and to respond to moral judgments. While philosophers in the Kantian tradition, who favor reason over sentiments, have generally been skeptical about this proposal, more recently, the claim that empathy is central for morality and a flourishing human life has again been the topic of an intense and controversial debate. On the one hand, empathy has been hailed by researchers from a wide range of disciplines and also by some public figures, President Obama most prominently among them. Slote (2010) champions empathy as the sole foundation of moral judgment, de Waal (2006) conceives of it as the unique evolutionary building block of morality, Rifkin (2009) regards it even as a force whose cultivation has unique revolutionary powers to transform a world in crisis, and Baron-Cohen (2011, 194) views it as a “universal solvent” in that “any problem immersed in empathy becomes soluble.” On the other hand, such empathy enthusiasm has encountered penetrating criticism by Prinz (2011a,b) and Bloom (2016), who emphasize its dark side, that is, its tendency to fall prey to so–called “here and now” biases. The following subsections will address these issues by surveying the relevant empirical research on the question of whether empathy motivates us selflessly, the question of whether empathy is inherently biased and partial to the in-group, and it will discuss how we might think of the normative character of moral judgments in light of our empathic capacities. (For a survey of other relevant issues from social psychology, specifically social neuroscience, consult also Decety and Lamm 2006; Decety and Ickes 2009, and Decety 20012. For a discussion of the importance of empathy for medical practice, see Halpern 2001)
4.1 Empathy and Altruistic Motivation
In a series of ingeniously designed experiments, Batson has accumulated evidence for what he calls the empathy-altruism thesis. In arguing for this thesis, Batson conceives of empathy as empathic concern or what others would call sympathy. More specifically, he characterized it in terms of feelings of being sympathetic, moved by, being compassionate, tender, warm and soft-hearted towards the other’s plight (Batson et al. 1987, 26) The task of his experiments consists in showing that empathy/sympathy does indeed lead to genuinely altruistic motivation, where the welfare of the other is the ultimate goal of my helping behavior, rather than to helping behavior because of predominantly egoistic motivations. According to the egoistic interpretation of empathy–related phenomena, empathizing with another person in need is associated with a negative feeling or can lead to a heightened awareness of the negative consequences of not helping, such as feelings of guilt, shame, or social sanctions. Alternatively, it can lead to an enhanced recognition of the positive consequences of helping behavior, such as social rewards or good feelings. Empathy, according to this interpretation, induces us to help through the mediation of purely egoistic motivations. We help others only because we recognize helping behavior as a means to egoistic ends. It allows us to reduce our negative feelings (aversive arousal reduction hypothesis), to avoid “punishment,” or to gain specific internal or external “rewards” (empathy-specific punishment and empathy-specific reward hypotheses).
Notice that in arguing for the empathy-altruism thesis, Batson is not claiming that empathy always induces helping behavior. Rather, he argues against the predominance of an egoistic interpretation of an agent’s motivational structure. He argues for the existence of genuinely altruistic motivations and, more specifically, for the claim that empathy causes such genuinely altruistic motivation. These genuinely altruistic motives (together with other egoistic motives) are taken into account by the individual agent in deliberating about whether or not to help. Even for Batson, the question of whether the agent will act on his or her altruistic motivations depends ultimately on how strong they are and what costs the agent would incur in helping another person.
In his experiments, Batson proceeds by manipulating the situation of the experimental subjects (dependent on the egoistic alternative to be argued against) and empathy/sympathy felt for an observed target in need. The decisive evidence for the empathy/sympathy-altruism thesis is always the recorded behavior of the subject, who is in a high empathy condition and in a situation where his helping behavior can not plausibly be seen as a means for the satisfaction of a personal goal. Since here is not the place to extensively describe the details of Batson’s experiments, a brief description of the experimental setup—focusing on Batson’s argument against the aversive arousal interpretation of empathy—and a brief evaluation of the success of his general argumentative strategy has to suffice (for more details see Batson 1991 and 2011). In all of his experiments, Batson assumes—based on Stotland (1969) and others—that empathy/sympathy can be manipulated either by manipulating the perceived similarity between subjects and targets or by manipulating the perspective-taking attitude of the subjects. Empathy can be increased by enhancing the perceived similarity between subject and target or by asking the subject to imagine how the observed person would feel in his or her situation rather than asking the subject to attend carefully to the information provided. [Note also that instructing the subject to imagine how they themselves would feel in the other’s situation, rather than instructing them to imagine how the other feels, is associated with an increase in personal distress and not only sympathetic feelings. (Batson et al. 1997b and Lamm, Batson, and Decety 2007).]
In trying to argue against the aversive arousal reduction interpretation, Batson also manipulates the ease with which a subject can avoid helping another person (in this case, taking his place when they see him getting electric shocks). He reasons that if empathy leads to genuinely altruistic motivations, subjects in the high empathy/easy escape condition should still be willing to help. If they were only helping in order to reduce their own negative feelings, they would be expected to leave in this situation, since leaving is the less costly means for reaching an egoistic goal. As Batson was happy to report, the results confirmed his empathy/sympathy-altruism hypothesis, not only in the above experiments but also in experiments testing other alternative interpretations of empathy, such as the empathy-specific punishment and the empathy-specific award hypotheses.
Researchers generally agree in finding Batson’s experimental research program and the accumulated evidence for the empathy-altruism thesis to be impressive. Yet they disagree about how persuasive one should ultimately regard his position. In particular, it has been pointed out that his experiments have limited value, since they target only very specific egoistic accounts of why empathy might lead to helping behavior. Batson is not able to dismiss conclusively every alternative egoistic interpretation. In addition, it has been claimed that egoism has the resources to account for the results of his experiments. For example, one might challenge the validity of Batson’s interpretation by speculating whether empathy/sympathy leads to a heightened awareness of the fact that one will be troubled by bad memories of seeing another person in need if one does nothing to help him or her. In this case, even an egoistically motivated person would help in the high empathy/easy escape condition. (For this reply and various other egoistic interpretations of Batson’s experiment,s see Sober and Wilson 1998, 264–271).
Cialdini and his collaborators have suggested an even more elaborate non-altruistic interpretation of helping behavior in high empathy/easy escape conditions. According to their suggestions, conditions of high empathy are also conditions of increased “interpersonal unity, wherein the conception of self and other are not distinct but are merged to some degree” (Cialdini et al. 1997, 490). It is this increased feeling of oneness rather than empathy that is causally responsible for motivating helping behavior (See Batson et al. 1997a, Neuberg et al. 1997, and Batson 1997 and 2011 for a plausible reply and May 2018, 144–153 for a probing discussion of the relation between empathic concern and oneness). One, therefore, has to be cautious in claiming that Batson has conclusively proven that the empathy/sympathy-altruism hypothesis is true, if that means one has logically excluded every egoistic alternative in accounting for helping behavior. But it has to be acknowledged that Batson has radically changed the argumentative dialectic of the egoism-altruism debate by forcing the egoistic account of human agency to come up with ever more elaborate alternative interpretations in order to account for helping behavior within its framework. Egoism was supposed to provide a rather unified and relatively simple account of the motivational structure of human agency. In challenging the predominance and simplicity of this framework in an empirically acute fashion, Batson has at least established altruism—claiming that besides egoistic motivations, we are also motivated by genuinely altruistic reasons—as an empirically plausible hypothesis. He has shown it to be a hypothesis that one is almost persuaded to believe is true, as he recently has characterized his own epistemic attitude (Batson 1997, 522). More positively expressed, Batson’s research has at least demonstrated that empathy/sympathy is a causal factor in bringing about helping behavior. Regardless of the question of the exact nature of the underlying motivation for helping or prosocial behavior, psychologists generally assume that in adults and children a positive, even if weak, correlation between empathy—measured in a variety of ways—and prosocial behavior has been established; and this even though the above aspects of emotional responding to another person have not always been sufficiently distinguished.(For a survey see Eisenberg and Miller 1987; Eisenberg/Fabes 1998, Spinrad and Eisenberg 2014. For a general survey of the various factors contributing to prosocial behavior see Bierhoff 2002).
Regardless of how exactly one views the strength of Batson’s position, his research alone does not validate the thesis articulated by various traditional moral philosophers, that sympathy or empathy is the basis of morality or that it constitutes the only source for moral motivation. First, nothing in his research has shown that empathy/sympathy is empirically necessary for moral agency. Second, some of Batson’s own research casts doubt on the claim that sympathy/empathy is the foundation of morality, since empathy-induced altruism can lead to behavior that conflicts with our principles of justice and fairness. One, for example, tends to assign a better job or a higher priority for receiving medical treatment to persons with whom one has sympathized, in violation of the above moral principles (See Batson et al. 1995). For that very reason, Batson himself distinguishes between altruistic motivation concerned with the well-being of another person and moral motivation guided by principles of justice and fairness (Batson 2011). Unfortunately, we do not always realize this fact when we abstractly contrast moral motivation broadly with egoistic motivation. For that very reason, we also do not realize that we need to be more conscious in “orchestrating” the relationship between altruistic and moral motivations in order to fully utilize the motivational power of altruism for moral purposes (Batson 2014). Finally, the research discussed so far is not relevant for deciding the question of whether sophisticated mindreading abilities are required for full-blown moral agency, since Batson understands empathy primarily as an emotional phenomenon. (See Nichols 2001 and Batson et al. 2003 in this respect.)
4.2 Empathy, Its Partiality, Susceptibility to Bias, and Moral Agency
Within the psychological literature, one of the most comprehensive accounts of empathy and its relation to the moral development of a person is provided by the work of Martin Hoffman (for a summary, see his 2000). Hoffman views empathy as a biologically based disposition for altruistic behavior (Hoffman 1981). He conceives of empathy as being due to various modes of arousal, allowing us to respond empathically in light of a variety of distress cues from another person. Hoffman mentions mimicry, classical conditioning, and direct association—where one empathizes because the other’s situation reminds one of one’s own painful experience—as “fast acting and automatic” mechanisms producing an empathic response. As more cognitively demanding modes, Hoffman lists mediated association—where the cues for an empathic response are provided in a linguistic medium—and role taking.
Hoffman distinguishes between six (or more) developmental stages of empathic responses, ranging from the reactive newborn cry, egocentric empathic distress, quasi-ego-centric empathic distress, to veridical empathy, empathy for another beyond the immediate situation, and empathy for whole groups of people. Accordingly, empathic responses constitute a developmental continuum that ranges from emotional contagion (as in the case of a reactive newborn cry) to various forms of proper empathy reached at the fourth stage. At the developmentally later stages, the child can emotionally respond to the distress of another in a more sophisticated manner due to an increase in cognitive capacities, particularly due to the increased cognitive ability to distinguish between self and other, and by becoming aware of the fact that others have mental states that are independent from its own. Only at the fourth stage of empathic development (after the middle of the second year) do children acquire such abilities. They no longer try to comfort themselves when emotionally responding to another child’s distress—like seeking comfort from their own mother—or use helping strategies that are more appropriate to comfort themselves than the other person—like using their own teddy bear in trying to comfort the other child. Only at the fourth stage does empathy become transformed or associated with sympathy, leading to appropriate prosocial behavior. Hoffman’s developmental view is further supported by Preston and DeWaal’s account of empathy as a phenomenon to be observed across species at various levels of complexity related to different degrees of cognitive development. (Preston and DeWaal 2002a,b. For a discussion of the philosophical relevance of DeWaal’s view, see also DeWaal 2006).
Significantly, Hoffman combines his developmental explication of empathy with a sophisticated analysis of its importance for moral agency. He is thereby acutely aware of the limitations in our natural capacity to empathize or sympathize with others, particularly what he refers to as “here and now” biases, that is, the fact that we tend to empathize more with persons that are in some sense perceived to be closer to us. (For a neuro-scientific investigation of how racial bias modulates empathic responses, see Xuo, Zuo, Wang, and Han 2009). Like Batson, Hoffman does not regard the moral realm as being exclusively circumscribed by our ability to empathize with other people. Besides empathic abilities, moral agency requires knowledge of abstract moral principles, such as the principles of caring and justice. Hoffman seems to conceive of those principles as being derived from cognitive sources that are independent of our empathic abilities. Yet Hoffmann is rather optimistic about the natural compatibility of empathic motivation and our commitment to moral principles. He regards stable and effective moral agency as requiring empathy so that moral principles can have a motivational basis in an agent’s psychology. Within this context, he has lately emphasized a final stage of empathy development or what he calls “witnessing”, an empathic response to the suffering of others that is so intense that we “become fully committed to help”(Hoffman 2014, 82). As he explains—in light of examples from the history of abolitionism, the civil rights movement, serfdom reform in Russia, and various cases before the Supreme Court— it is particularly such witnessing that has contributed towards bending the arc of the moral universe towards justice. Accordingly, and despite our natural limitations in empathizing with others, Hoffman still regards empathy as the “bedrock of morality” and “the glue of society”(Hoffman 2014, 96. Besides Hoffman 2011 and 2014, see also Deigh 2011 for a measured evaluation of empathy in the legal context).
More recently, such a positive evaluation of empathy’s contributing role in constituting us as moral agents, as agents who address each other from the moral stance, has encountered penetrating criticism, particularly by Prinz (2011a,b), Bloom (2016), and Breithaupt 2019 (For a more moderate formulation of his negative stance toward empathy see also Bloom 2022). All of them emphasize the dark side of empathy, that is, the aforementioned “here and now” biases. More specifically, Prinz mentions explicitly the cuteness, salience, and proximity effects—the fact that we tend to empathize more easily with attractive persons, with persons that are in close proximity and only if their suffering is particularly noteworthy— similarity biases, and the fact that we tend to be rather selective in choosing whom to empathize with. Empathy is also very easily modulated by a variety of top-down factors that influence our perception of the social world and that let us register social divisions that seem to be prima facie incompatible with the more impartial stance demanded by the moral perspective. Research has documented these biases in a more fine-grained manner and shown that subjects generally “reported experiencing more empathy for the in–group then the out–group targets and more counter–empathy for the out–group than in–group targets”(Cikara et. al. 2014, 120), counter–empathy here being understood as the feeling of pleasure at the misfortune of another (Schadenfreude) or the feeling displeasure at something fortunate happening to another (Glückschmerz). This is particularly true if the other group is viewed to be in competition with one’s own group. Empathy can also be further reduced through various dehumanizing and objectifying strategies, strategies that have certainly been employed in the context of the genocides of the twentieth century and the system of racial slavery in the United States (See Fuchs 2019, Kteily and Bruneau 2017). Heightened empathy for perceived wrongs done to members of the in–group can also lead to violent and immoral behavior (Bloom 2016, chap. 5). In addition, empathy tends to focus on the one (particularly if he or she is identifiable) rather than the many, what Bloom refers to as its spotlight feature. Empathy can mislead us particularly in contexts where we need to take into account statistically relevant information when addressing a moral or social problem, such as when thinking about the benefits of vaccination, where it is more appropriate to think about the large numbers of children saved rather than empathizing with the bad effects such vaccination might have on one specific child. For all of these reasons, Prinz favors the moral emotions such as anger, guilt and shame as the foundation for morality, while Bloom prefers sympathy guided by reason as a more viable means than empathy to steer us in moral matters (Breithaupt 2019 has a nuanced evaluation of empathy: He suggests that we should evaluate empathy less from the moral stance but think of the positive contribution of empathy in terms of broadening one’s narrow perspective and intensifying one’s asethetic engagement with the world).
Here is not the place for a final evaluation of empathy’s contribution in regard to pro-social and moral motivation or moral and pro-social behavior, since this question is still very much the topic of an ongoing empirical investigation. Yet the following observations are certainly justified in light of the empirical evidence so far and might help to clarify the debate further. First, it seems to be pretty well established that, however one defines our natural capacity for empathy, it is on its own not sufficient to keep us reliably on the path of morality (See also Decety and Cowell 2015). Whether that ultimately means we should consider our capacity for empathy as a limited resource or whether it would be better to view empathy as a motivated phenomenon, with its limitations stemming from our reluctance to activate that capacity (Zaki 2014), is certainly another intriguing question for further empirical inquiry. One might also wonder why we should expect that the emotions such as sympathy and anger, which Bloom and Prinz point to, are less prone to bias and less affected by a universal human tendency to favor the in–group. Certainly, sympathy within the context of Buddhism, to which Bloom appeals to is a highly regulated emotion, controlled through mindfulness practices or meditation and guided by an intellectual grasp about the detriments of various forms of attachment to this world. Persson and Savulescu (2018) therefore suggest that rather than giving up on empathy completely one should reform empathy by regulating it through one’s reflective capacities in light of our knowledge of its natural shortcomings or focus one’s empathy (cognitive and affective) particularly on another person’s concerns for his or her well-being as such empathy includes sympathy for the other (Simmons 2014). Such suggestions are also very much in line with proposals by David Hume and Adam Smith, who suggested already in the eighteenth century that we need to regulate empathy with the help of certain corrective mechanisms such as “some steady and general points of view” or the perspective of the“impartial spectator” to compensate for empathy’s limited scope. (For a good analysis of the philosophical discussion about empathy/sympathy in the eighteenth century, see Frazer 2010).
Most importantly, in order to evaluate the empirical discussion about empathy’s role for morality, one needs to be very sensitive to how researchers define and measure empathy. Prinz and Bloom are quite explicit in defining empathy merely as an affective phenomenon, as our ability to feel what the other person feels. Evidence suggests indeed that merely sharing another person’s emotion empathically does not increase our concern or motivation for moral or pro-social action. Interestingly, however, perspective–taking and empathic concern/sympathy, which have always been seen as an integral part of empathy-related phenomena, are a slightly different matter. They do seem to be positively related to cooperation and charitable giving (Jordon et. al. 2016), to reducing prejudices against particular groups (Galinski and Morowitz 2011), and to an increase in one’s sensitivity to injustices done to others (Decety and Yoder 2015). Yet even here, further research is needed as the effects of such perspective–taking could be modulated by the power differential between groups. It has, for example, been shown that in active intergroup conflicts, positive intergroup interaction can increase empathy for the other group. Yet within such contexts, taking the perspective of a person from the other group while interacting with them might also hinder the development of intergroup empathy if the dominant group is reminded through such perspective–taking of how they might be viewed by the non-dominant group. Even perspective taking by the non–dominant group might increase rather than decrease established negative stereotypes in thinking about the other group (Cikara et. al. 2014). It seems more effective if the non–dominant group is asked to articulate the difficulties of their lives (perspective–giving) and the dominant group is asked to translate that description into their own words (perspective–taking), even if the positive effects of such interaction are relatively short-lived (Bruneau and Saxe 2012). Finally, despite all of its problems, we probably can’t imagine living a human and humane life without empathy. How else would it be possible to establish deep emotional interpersonal relations that form the basis of relations between friends, members of a family, and form the foundation of human solidarity (in this respect, see Bailey 2022, Betzler 2019, and Song 2015). While it is true that such solidarity does not automatically have a universal scope, it is unlikely that we would feel any obligations toward others without practicing it first in small-scale societies.
4.3 Empathy, Moral Judgment, and the Authority of Moral Norms
So far, this entry has discussed mainly research exploring the relation between empathy and prosocial/moral behavior or motivation. Other important areas for considering empathy’s role in moral matters have to do with addressing the questions of how and whether empathy contributes to our ability to distinguish between moral and conventional norms, to the making of moral judgments, and how empathy can be appealed to in explicating the normative authority of such judgments. In considering the first question, psychologists and philosophers have generally followed Turiel in understanding moral norms as expressing concerns for “rights, justice, and the welfare of other people” (Turiel 1983, 3) and as having a very specific “signature response patterns” (Kelly et. al. 2007) associated with it. Moral norms are generally regarded to be more important than conventional norms in that their normative validity is conceived as being independent of social authority or specific social practices and agreements. Their scope is also judged to be much broader—they are thought to be valid in other countries, for example— and violation of moral norms is generally understood to be a more serious offense than the violation of other norms. Notice that in distinguishing between moral and conventional norms, subjects do not necessarily associate a strict universality in the Kantian sense with moral norms and view them as applicable to all rational beings. Indeed, there is some evidence that 6–9-year-old children, for example, view the moral/conventional distinction as being fully applicable only to the behavior of individuals in the in-group and view prescription against harming members of the out-group to be more like conventional norms (Rhodes and Chalik 2013). Accordingly, the fact that empathy shows considerable in-group bias, as discussed above, does not automatically count as evidence against it playing a role in allowing humans to distinguish between moral and conventional norms within a social context.
Of central importance for assessing the role of empathy for grasping the moral/conventional distinction has been the research on the nature of psychopathy and autism. Both pathologies are seen as involving deficits in different dimensions of empathy. Yet only psychopaths have great difficulties in living up to moral standards of their societies, and only they were originally thought of as having difficulties in appropriately distinguishing between moral and conventional norms (Blair 1995 and 1996). More specifically, psychopaths show a selective deficit in affective or emotional empathy, particularly in “processing fearful, sad, and possibly disgusted facial expressions”(Blair 2010, 710). In contrast to persons with autism, they do not show similar deficits in perspective-taking or theory of mind capacities. In his 1995 article, Blair therefore blames the absence of what he calls the Violence Inhibition Mechanism(VIM) that allows us to respond appropriately to the observed distress cues in others for the psychopaths’ moral deficits and their inability to draw the moral/conventional distinction. In his later work, he speaks more broadly of a dysfunction of our Integrated Emotion System (IES), caused by a deficit in the amygdala to properly represent negative emotions. (Blair, Mitchel, and Blair 2005, for a recent survey regarding the very specific deficit of psychopaths in feeling and recognizing fear, see also Marsh 2014). Yet one has to tread very carefully in drawing definite conclusions about the role of empathy for morality from the empirical research about psychopathy. The results of the empirical investigations are far from unified and do not point in the same direction (For a concise survey, see Maibom 2017). Newer studies, for example, seem to suggest that psychopaths, as measured by the overall score of the revised psychopathy checklist (PCL–R), are able to understand the distinction between moral and conventional norms if tested under a forced choice paradigm (Aharoni et. al, 2012). Nevertheless, even that study seems to allow for the possibility that emotional deficits are responsible for the psychopath’s shortcomings in accurately drawing the distinction since they are somewhat linked to the affective and antisocial facets of the PCL–R. Given the inconsistent results of the various studies, other researchers prefer to view a psychopath’s immorality not as a specific deficit in empathy, but understand it to be caused by their general inability to feel strong emotions, by their general coldheartedness, or even by shortcomings in their rational and prudential capacities. From that perspective, a psychopath might understand in an abstract manner that certain things are morally wrong to do, but he just does not care about morality, the welfare of another person, or even for himself. (For further discussion, see Maibom 2005 and 2009, Nichols 2004, and Prinz 2011a,b). Similar considerations also apply to research regarding subjects with autism. Kennett (2002)has argued that evidence from autistic individuals, whose imaginative role-play and thus empathic capacities are diminished, does not support the claim that empathy is necessary for moral agency. Yet in her arguments, she only considers the fact that persons with autism have difficulties with putting themselves in another person’s shoes, but does not consider that they seem to have some ability to pick up on the emotional states of other people as revealed by their facial expressions. Moreover, while autistic subjects in general can distinguish between moral and conventional norms, they do seem to lack a certain flexibility in evaluating the seriousness of the violation of a moral norm when they reflect on moral dilemmas or when they encounter an accidental or unintentional violation of such norms. (See McGeer 2008, Zalla et. al 2011, but see also Kennett 2011 and Leslie et. al. 2006 in response).
Philosophers have not only been interested in appealing to empathy for explicating the psychological basis for our thinking that certain norms have moral status. Within the general framework of moral sentimentalism, which sees morality generally linked to our emotional responsiveness to the actions of others and ourselves, they have also appealed to empathy in explicating more generally the nature of moral judgments (see also Kauppinen 2014 and 2017a). David Hume, for example, has suggested that moral judgments are based on peculiar sentiments of moral approbation and disapprobation, which are causally mediated by our ability to empathize— or what he called sympathy— with the pain and pleasures of others (See also Sayre-McCord 1994 and 2014). More specifically, sentiments of moral approbations arise in response to our ability to think about and enliven the pleasure and pain that others feel with the help of our empathic/sympathetic capacities when we consider the benefits (the pleasure and pain) that a person’s character traits and actions provide to himself and others. Yet Hume was already quite aware of some of the above-mentioned limitations and biases of our natural willingness and capacity to empathize with others. Accordingly, he insisted that sentiments of approbations can only be conceived of as moral approbation if empathy/sympathy is regulated or corrected by what he refers to as “steady and general points of view” (Hume 1739–40 [1978], 581/2) so that our capacity for sympathy enables us to “touch a string, to which all mankind have an accord and symphony” (Hume 1748 [1983], 75). There are several issues that can be raised in response to Hume’s proposal. Suffice it here to point out that it is difficult to fully understand how Hume is ultimately able distinguish between judgments about something being bad and something being morally wrong. Certainly, natural disasters also cause us to sympathize/empathize with the pain it cause others, yet such sympathy does not mediate any judgments about the moral impermissibility of natural disasters. Hume himself might have thought that he had solved this problem by thinking that sentiments of moral approbation have a peculiar or distinct character (see particularly Debes 2012). Yet pointing to the peculiarity of such sentiments seems to be rather unsatisfying for answering this challenge.
Michael Slote, one of the main contemporary proponents of the claim that empathy plays a constitutive role for moral judgments, does not follow Hume in thinking that empathy plays a moral role in allowing us to pick up on a subject’s pleasure and pain. Rather, Slote, who also has been influenced by a feminist ethics of care (Slote 2007, 2010), suggests that empathy is central for moral approval in that we as spectators empathically pick up on whether or not an agent acted out of empathic concern for another subject. Moral approval of an action consists then in the subsequent reflective feeling of warmth when empathizing with an agent’s empathic concern, while moral disapproval is equivalent to a reflective feeling of chill due to our recognition that the agent acted without any empathic concern. Actions are then judged to be morally right or wrong in terms of whether they can be conceived as the actions of an agent we would morally approve of in that they are actions done out of empathic concern. Notice also that while Slote does regard empathy in the above sense to be constitutive of moral approval only if it is fully or well–developed, he does not follow Hume in thinking that empathy needs to be regulated in order to correct for some of its natural partiality. Indeed, Slote thinks that this is a virtue of his account since he regards such partiality as reflected in our moral intuitions. For example, he thinks that we have a greater moral obligation to help the child in front of us or members of our family rather than people who are more removed from us. Slote certainly deserves credit for reviving the debate about the role of empathy for morality in contemporary metaethics. Yet his conception of the relation between empathy and morality has also encountered some skepticism. First of all, it is questionable that only motivations of empathic concern, rather than the thought that one is doing the right thing, constitute proper moral motivations. Second, in light of the above research on empathy’s bias and natural shortcomings, it is rather questionable to maintain that all aspects of empathy’s partiality are sanctioned by our moral intuitions. It is therefore hard to see how empathy’s moral role can be justified without appeal to some form of corrective mechanism. (For further discussion, fundamentally challenging the psychological plausibility of Slote’s account, see D’Arms 2011, Kauppinen 2014 and 2017a, and Prinz 2001a,b).
There is one additional element to consider when debating empathy’s contribution to morality. Philosophers are not merely interested in answering factual and causal questions of why we care about morality, what causal role empathy plays in this respect, or how empathy causally contributes to allowing us to distinguish between moral and conventional norms and to judge what is morally right or wrong. They are also interested in genuinely normative questions in attempting to answer the question of why we should care about morality and why we should regard moral judgments as making normative demands on us. In morally blaming other persons, we do assume that we evaluate their behavior according to standards that they as persons are in some sense already committed to. We assume that these standards are their own standards rather than standards that we impose from an external perspective on them. Unfortunately, even if one would agree with either David Hume or Michael Slote’s account of the causal role of empathy outlined above, it is doubtful that their account would help us to answer the genuinely normative question appropriately. Why exactly should I take a particular emotional reaction of another person towards me and my action, even if it is a feeling of warmth caused by empathy, as something that is normatively relevant for me? Certainly, we all like to be liked and try to fit in with our peer group, but then moral judgments would be nothing more than a glorified form of peer pressure. Hume might respond that we should take them seriously because they are responses from the general point of view, but that in itself seems to be begging the question of why such a perspective is articulating the appropriate normative standard for judging our behavior and character (For an attempt to ground morality without appeal to an impartial perspective in light of phenomenological reflections on empathy and sympathy, see however Drummond 2022). This is also exactly the reason why philosophers with Kantian inclinations have been skeptical about moral sentimentalism and positions that think of empathy as a foundation of morality (for a nice explication of Kant’s critical view of sympathy, see Deimling 2017). Contemporary “Kantians” do at times, however, admit that empathy and perspective-taking are epistemically relevant for moral deliberations, even if it is not solely constitutive for moral agency (Deigh 1996 and 2018; Darwall 2006, Shermann 1998, For a review see also Oxley 2011). Interestingly, philosophers sympathetic to moral sentimentalism have particularly turned to Adam Smith for inspiration in developing empathy-based accounts of morality and in responding to the above normativity problem. In contrast to Hume, Smith conceives of empathy/sympathy not merely as the enlivening of a perceived emotion or feeling but as imaginative perspective–taking. In taking up another person’s perspective, we put ourselves in his situation and imagine how he would respond to the situation, how he would think and feel about it. If, in bringing another person’s point of view “home to ourselves” in this manner, we recognize that we ourselves might have felt or acted like the other person, then we approve of the other person’s sentiment or action; otherwise, we disapprove. Moreover, such approval constitutes moral approval if we have empathized with the other from the perspective of the impartial spectator, a perspective that Smith, like Hume, appeals to in order to correct for empathy’s natural shortcomings. More importantly, some authors think that within the Smithian framework, we also find some answers to the normativity problem. They think that the impartial spectator perspective can be recast as an implicit commitment of our ordinary practice of making sense of each other as rational and emotional creatures with the help of empathic perspective taking (Stueber 2017) or argue that Smithian perspective–taking involves quasi-Kantian commitments to the dignity of a person, including his or her affective dimension. (Debes 2017, Fleischacker 2019, Fricke 2005, Kauppinen 2017b, and Roughley 2018).
Bibliography
Cited Works
- Abel, T., 1948, “The Operation Called Verstehen”, The American Journal of Sociology, 54: 211–18; reprinted in Dallmayr, Fred and Thomas McCarthy (eds.), Understanding and Social Inquiry, Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press, 1977.
- Aharoni, E., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., and Kiehl, K.A., 2012, “Can Psychopathic Offenders Discern Moral Wrong? A New Look at the Moral/Conventional Distinction”, Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 121: 484–497.
- Allen, C., 2010, “Mirror, Mirror in the Brain, what’s the Monkey Stand to Gain?”, Noûs, 44: 372–391.
- Bailey, O., 2022, “Empathy and the Value of Humane Understanding”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 104: 50–65.
- Baron-Cohen, S., 2003, The Essential Difference: The Truth about the Male and Female Brain, New York: Basic Books.
- –––, 2011, The Science of Evil: On Empathy and the Origins of Cruelty, New York: Basic Books.
- Baron-Cohen, S. and S. Wheelwright, 2004, “The Empathy Quotient: An Investigation of Adults with Asperger Syndrome or High Functioning Autism, and Normal Sex Differences”, Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 34: 163–175.
- Batson, C.D., 1991, The Altruism Question: Toward a Social Psychological Answer, Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
- –––, 1997, “Self-Other Merging and the Empathy-Altruism Hypothesis: Reply to Neuberg et al.”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 73: 517–522.
- –––, 2009, “These Things Called Empathy: Eight Related But Distinct Phenomena”, in J. Decety and W. Ickes (eds.), The Social Neuroscience of Empathy, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 3–15.
- –––, 2011, Altruism in Humans, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2014, “Empathy–Induced Altruism and Morality: No Necessary Connection,” in H. Maibom (ed.), Empathy and Morality, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 41–58.
- Batson, C.D., J. Fultz, and P. Schoenrade, 1987, “Distress and Empathy: Two Qualitatively Distinct Vicarious Emotions with Different Motivational Consequences”, Journal of Personality, 55: 19–39.
- Batson, C.D., R.R. Klein, L. Highberger, and L.L. Shaw, 1995, “Immorality From Empathy-Induced Altruism: When Compassion and Justice Conflict”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 68: 1042–1054.
- Batson, C.D., K. Sager, E. Garst, M. Kang, K. Rubchinsky, and K. Dawson, 1997a, “Is Empathy Induced Helping Due to Self-Other Merging?”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 73: 495–509.
- Batson, C.D., S. Early, and G.Salvarini, 1997b, “Perspective Taking: Imagining how Another Feels versus Imagining how You Would Feel”, Personality and Social Personality Bulletin, 23: 751–758.
- Batson, C.D., D. Lishner, A.Carpenter, L. Dulin, S. Harjusola-Webb, E. L. Stocks, S. Gale, O. Hassan, and B. Sampat, 2003, “‘…As you Would Have Them Do Unto You’: Does Imagining Yourself in the Other’s Place Stimulate Moral Action?”, Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 29: 1190–1201.
- Berninger, A., 2024, “Experience and Understanding in Response to Holocaust Testimony”, in T. Petraschka and C. Werner (eds.), Empathy’s Role in Understanding Persons, Literature, and Art, London and New York: Routledge, pp. 84–102.
- Betzler, M. 2019, “The Relational Value of Empathy”, International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 27: 136–161.
- Betzler, M. and S. Keller, 2021, “Shared Belief and the Limits of Empathy”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 102(2): 267–291.
- Bierhoff, H.-W., 2002, Prosocial Behavior, East Sussex: Psychology Press.
- Blair, R., 1996, “Brief Report: Morality in the Autistic Child”, Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 26: 571–579.
- Blair, R., D. Mitchell, and D. Blair, 2005, The Psychopath, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.
- Bloom, P., 2016, Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion, New York: Ecco.
- –––, 2022, “Empathy and Its Critics”, in T. DuJardin and M. D. Eckel (eds.), Faith, Hope, and Love: The Theological Virtues and Their Opposites, Cham: Springer, pp. 177–187.
- Blum, L., 1980, “Compassion”, in A. Rorty (ed.), Explaining Emotions, Berkeley and Los Angeles, University of California Press.
- Boisserie-Lacroix, C. and M. Inchingolo, 2021, “Empathy for a Reason: From Understanding Agency to Phenomenal Insight”, Synthese, 198: 7097–7118.
- Borg, E., 2007, “If Mirror Neurons Are the Answer, What was the Question?”, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 14: 5–19.
- Breithaupt, F., 2009, Kulturen der Empathie, Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.
- –––, 2019, The Dark Sides of Empathy, Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press.
- Bruneau, E. and R. Saxe, 2012, “The Power of Being Heard: The Benefits of ‘Perspective-Giving’ in the Context of Intergroup Conflict”, Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 48: 855–866.
- Cassam, Q., 2018, “The Epistemology of Terrorism and Radicalisation”, Royal Institute of Philosophy (Supplement), 84: 187–209.
- –––, forthcoming, “Engaging with the Subjectivity of Extremists: What, How, and Why”, in Rik Peels and Quassim Cassam (eds.), Extremism and Subjectivity: Extremist, Academic, and Practitioner Perspectives, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Cath, Y., 2019, “Knowing What It Is Like and Testimony”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 97(1): 105–120.
- Choplan, B., M. McCain, J. Carbonell, and R. Hagen, 1985, “Empathy: Review of Available Measures”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 48: 635–653.
- Churchland, P., 1970, “The Logical Character of Action-Explanations”, The Philosophical Review, 79: 214–236.
- Cialdini, R.B., S.L. Brown, B.P. Lewis, C. Luce, and S.L. Neuberg, 1997, “Reinterpreting the Empathy-Altruism Relationship: When One Into One Equals Oneness”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 73: 481–494.
- Cikara, M., E. Bruneau, J.J. Van Bavel, and R. Saxe, 2014, “Their Pain Gives Us Pleasure: How Intergroup Dynamics Shape Empathic Failures and Counter–Empathic Responses”, Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 55: 110–115.
- Clavel-Vazquez, M.J. and A. Clavel-Vazquez, 2023, “Robustly Embodied Imagination and the Limits of Perspective-Taking”, Philosophical Studies, 180: 1395–1420.
- Collingwood, R.G., 1946. The Idea of History, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Coplan, A., 2011, “Understanding Empathy: Its Features and Effects”, in A. Coplan and P. Goldie (eds.), Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 3–18.
- Coplan, A., and P. Goldie (eds.), 2011, Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Cronbach, L., 1955, “Processes Affecting Scores on ‘Understanding of Others’ and ‘Assumed Similarity’”. Psychological Bulletin, 52: 177–193.
- Csibra, F., 2007, “Action Mirroring and Action Interpretation: An Alternative Account,” in P. Haggard, Y. Rosetti and M. Kawato, (eds.), Sensorimotor Foundations of Higher Cognition (Attention and Performance XII), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 435–459.
- Currie, G., and I. Ravenscroft, 2002, Recreative Minds, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Curtis, R. and G. Koch, 2009, Einfühlung: Zur Geschichte und Gegenwart eines ästhetischen Konzepts, München: Wilhelm Fink Verlag.
- Danto, Arthur, 1965, Analytical Philosophy of History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- D’Arms, J., 2011, “Empathy, Approval, and Disapproval in Moral Sentimentalism”, Southern Journal of Philosophy (Supplementary Volume), 49: 134–141.
- Darwall, S., 1998, “Empathy, Sympathy, and Care”, Philosophical Studies, 89: 261–282.
- –––, 2006, The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
- Davies M., and T. Stone (eds.), 1995, Folk Psychology, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
- Davis, M., 1980, “A Multidimensional Approach to Individual Differences in Empathy”, JSAS Catalog of Selected Documents in Psychology, 10: 85.
- –––, 1983, “Measuring Individual Differences in Empathy: Evidence for a Multidimensional Approach”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 44: 113–126.
- –––, 1994, Empathy: A Social Psychological Approach, Boulder: Westview Press.
- Davis, M. and L. Kraus, 1997, “Personality and Empathic Accuracy,” in W. Ickes (ed.), Empathic Accuracy, New York/London: Guilford Press, 144–168.
- Debes, R., 2010, “Which Empathy? Limitations in the Mirrored ”Understanding“ of Emotions”, Synthese, 175: 219–239.
- –––, 2012, “Recasting Scottish Sentimentalism: The Pecularity of Moral Approval”, Journal of Scottish Philosophy, 10(1): 91–115.
- –––, 2017. “The Authority of Empathy (Or How to Ground Sentimentalism)”, in R. Debes and K. Stueber (eds.), Ethical Sentimentalism: New Perspectives, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 171–191.
- Decety, J. 2010, “To What Extent is the Experience of Empathy Mediated by Shared Neural Circuits?”, Emotion Review, 2(3): 204–207.
- –––, 2012, Empathy: From Bench to Bedside, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Decety, J. and J.M. Cowell, 2015., “Empathy, Justice, and Moral Behavior”, AJOB Neuroscience, 6: 3–14.
- Decety, J. and C. Lamm, 2006, “Human Empathy through the Lens of Social Neuroscience”, The Scientific World Journal, 6: 1146–1163.
- Decety, J. and W. Ickes, 2009 (eds.), The Social Neuroscience of Empathy, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Decety, J. and K.J. Joder, 2016, “Empathy and Motivation for Justice: Cognitive Empathy and Concern, But Not Emotional Empathy, Predict Sensitivity to Injustice for Others”, Social Neuroscience, 11: 1–14.
- Deigh, J., 1996, “Empathy and Universalizability,” in Mind and Morals, L. May, M. Friedman and A. Clark (eds.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 199–219.
- –––, 2011, “Empathy, Justice, and Jurisprudence”, The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 49 (Spindel Supplement): 73–90.
- –––, 2018, “Is Empathy Required for Making Moral Judgment?”, in N. Roughley and T. Schramme (eds.), Forms of Fellow Feeling: Empathy, Sympathy and Moral Agency, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 245–264.
- Deimling, W., 2017, “Hutchinson’s and Kant’s Critique of Sympathy”, in E. Robinson and C.W. Suprenant (eds.), Kant and the Scottish Enlightenment, New York: Routledge, pp. 55–780.
- Deonna, J.A., 2007, “The Structure of Empathy”, Journal of Moral Philosophy, 4: 99–116.
- De Waal, Fr., 2006, Primates and Philosophers: How Morality Evolved, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
- –––, 2009, The Age of Empathy: Nature’s Lessons for a Kinder Society, New York: Random House.
- DeVignemont, F., and T. Singer, 2006. “The Empathic Brain: How, When, and Why?”, Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10: 435–441.
- Dilthey, W., 1961–, Gesammelte Schriften, 15 vols. Leipzig: Teubner Verlagsgesellschaft.
- Dray, W., 1957, Laws and Explanation in History, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- –––, 1995, History as Re-enactment, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Droysen, J.G., 1977, Historik, Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog.
- Drummond, J. , 2022. “Sympathetic Respect, Respectful Sympathy”, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 25: 123–137.
- Dymont, R., 1949, “A Scale of Measurement of Empathic Ability”, Journal of Consulting Psychology, 13: 127–133.
- Eisenberg, N., 2000a. “Empathy and Sympathy,” M. Lewis and J.M. Haviland-Jones (eds.), Handbook of Emotions, New York/London: Guilford Press, 677–691.
- –––, 2000b, “Emotion, Regulation, and Moral Development”, Annual Review of Psychology, 51: 665–697.
- Eisenberg, N., and J. Strayer (eds.), 1987, Empathy and Its Development, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Eisenberg, N., and P.A. Miller, 1987, “Empathy, Sympathy, and Altruism: Empirical and Conceptual Links,” in N. Eisenberg and J. Strayer (eds.), Empathy and Its Development, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 292–316.
- Eisenberg, N. and R. Fabes, 1998, “Prosocial Development,” in W. Damon and N. Eisenberg (eds.), Handbook of Child Psychology (Volume 3: Social, Emotional and Personality Development), New York: Wiley, pp. 701–778.
- Eisenberg, N., B. Murphy, and S. Shepard, 1997, “The Development of Empathic Accuracy”, in W. Ickes (ed.), Empathic Accuracy, New York/London: Guilford Press, pp. 73–116.
- Feest, U. (ed.), 2012, “Current Topics in the Philosophy of the Human Sciences”, Inquiry, 55 (1), Special Issue.
- Fiebich, A., Gallagher, S., and D.D. Hutto, 2017, “Pluralism, Interaction, and the Ontogeny of Social Cognition”, in J Kiverstein (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of the Social Mind, New York: Routledge, pp. 208–221.
- Fleischacker, S., 2019, Being Me Being You: Adam Smith and Empathy, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Frazer, M., 2010, The Enlightenment of Sympathy: Justice and the Moral Sentiments in the Eighteenth Century and Today, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Fricke, C., 2005, “Genesis und Geltung moralischer Normen: Ein Gedankenexperiment von Adam Smith”, in C. Fricke and H.P. Schütt (eds.), Adam Smith als Moralphilosoph, Berlin/New York: DeGruyter, 33–63.
- Frith, U., and C.D. Frith, 2003, “Development and Neurophysiology of Mentalizing”, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society (Series B), 358: 459–473.
- Fuchs, T., 2019., “Empathy, Group Identity, and the Mechanisms of Exclusion: An Investigation into the Limits of Empathy”, Topoi, 38: 239–250.
- Gadamer, H.-G., 1989, Truth and Method, New York: Crossroad Publishing.
- Gallagher, S., 2012, “Neurons, Neonates, and Narrative: From Embodied Resonance to Empathic Understanding”, in A. Foolen, U, Lüdtke, t. Racine and J. Zlatev (eds.), Moving Ourselves, Moving Others: Motion and Emotion in Intersubjectivity, Consciousness, and Language, Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company, 165–196.
- Gallagher, S., and D. Hutto, 2008, “Understanding Others Through Primary Interaction and Narrative Practice”, in J. Zlatev, T. Racine, C. Sinha, and E. Itkonen (eds.), The Shared Mind: Perspectives on Intersubjectivity, Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company, pp. 17–38.
- Gallese, V., 2001, “The ‘Shared Manifold’ Hypothesis: From Mirror Neurons to Empathy”, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8: 33–50.
- –––, 2003a, “The Roots of Empathy: The Shared Manifold Hypothesis and the Neural Basis of Intersubjectivity”, Psychopathology, 36: 171–180.
- –––, 2003b, “The Manifold Nature of Interpersonal Relations: The Quest for a Common Mechanism,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, 358: 517–528.
- –––, 2016, “Finding the Body in the Brain: From Simulation Theory to Embodied Simulation,” in B. McLaughlin and H.K. Kornblith (eds.), Goldman and His Critics, Oxford: Wiley, pp. 297–314.
- Gallese, V., C. Keysers, and G. Rizzolatti, 2004, “A Unifying View of the Basis of Social Cognition”, Trends in Cognitive Science, 8: 396–403.
- Galinsky, A. and G. Moskowitz, 2001, “Perspective Taking: Decreasing Stereotype Expression, Stereotype Accessibility, and In–Group Favoritism”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78: 708–724.
- Gazzola, V., L. Aziz-Zadeh, and C. Keysers, 2006, “Empathy and the Somatotopic Auditory Mirror System in Humans”, Current Biology, 16: 1824–1829.
- Goldie, P., 2000, The Emotions, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2011, “Anti-Empathy,” in A. Coplan and P. Goldie (eds.), Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 302–317.
- Goldman, A., 2002, “Simulation Theory and Mental Concepts”, in J. Dokic and J. Proust (eds.), Simulation and Knowledge of Action, Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company, pp. 1–19.
- –––, 2006, Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2009, “Mirroring, Simulating, and Mindreading,” Mind and Language, 24: 235–252.
- –––, 2011, “Two Routes to Empathy: Insights from Cognitive Neuroscience”, in A. Coplan and P. Goldie (eds.), Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 31–44.
- Gordon, Robert M., 1995a. “The Simulation Theory: Objections and Misconceptions,” in M. Davies and T. Stone (eds.), Folk Psychology, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, pp. 100–122.
- –––, 1995b, “Simulation Without Introspection from Me to You”, in M. Davies and T. Stone (eds.), Mental Simulation, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, pp. 53–67.
- –––, 2000, “Sellars’s Rylean Revisited”. Protosoziologie, 14: 102–114.
- Gopnik, A., and A.N. Meltzoff, 1997, Words, Thoughts and Theories: Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Greif, E. and R. Hogan, 1973, “The Theory and Measurement of Empathy”, Journal of Counseling Psychology, 20: 280–284.
- Grimm, S., 2016, “How Understanding People Differs from Understanding the Natural World,” Philosophical Issues (Noûs Supplement), 26: 209–225.
- Grimm, S., C. Baumberger, and S. Ammon, 2017, Explaining Understanding: New Perspectives from Epistemology and Philosophy of Science, New York: Routledge.
- Grondin, J., 1994, Introduction to Philosophical Hermeneutics, New Haven: Yale University Press.
- Hannon, M., 2020, “Empathetic Understanding and Deliberative Democracy”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 101(3): 591–611.
- –––, 2025, “Social Identity, Understanding, and Deference”, Philosophical Studies, first online 20 June 2025. doi:10.1007/s11098-025-02364-2
- Hartmann, M., 2023, The Feeling of Inequality: On Empathy, Empathy Gulfs, and the Political Psychology of Democracy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Halpern, J., 2001, From Detached Concern to Empathy: Humanizing Medical Practice, New York: Oxford University Press.
- Heal, J., 2003, Mind, Reason and Imagination, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Heider, F., 1958, The Psychology of Interpersonal Relations, New York: Wiley.
- Hempel, C., 1965, Aspects of Scientific Explanations, New York: Free Press.
- Henderson, D., 1993, Interpretation and Explanation in the Human Sciences, Albany: State University of New York Press.
- –––, 2011, “Let’s Be Flexible: Our Interpretive/Explanatory Toolbox, or In Praise of Using a Range of Tools,” Journal of the Philosophy of History, 5: 261–299.
- Henderson, D., and T. Horgan, 2000, “Simulation and Epistemic Competence,” in H.H. Kögler and K. Stueber (eds.), Empathy and Agency: The Problem of Understanding in the Human Sciences, Boulder: Westview Press, pp. 119–143.
- Hickok, G., 2008, “Eight Problems for the Mirror Neuron Theory of Action Understanding in Monkeys and Humans”, Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 21: 1229–1243.
- –––, 2014, The Myth of Mirror Neurons: The Real Neuroscience of Cognition and Communication, New York: W.W. Norton and Company.
- Hoffman, M., 1981, “Is Altruism Part of Human Nature?”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 40: 121–137.
- –––, 2000, Empathy and Moral Development, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- –––, 2011, “Empathy, Justice and the Law”, in A. Coplan and P. Goldie (eds.), Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 230–254.
- –––, 2014, “Empathy, Justice and Social Change”, in H. Maibom (ed.), Empathy and Morality, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 71–96.
- Hogan, R., 1969, “Development of an Empathy Scale”, Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 33: 307–316.
- Hollan, D.W., 2012, “Emerging Issues in the Cross-Cultural Study of Empathy”, Emotion Review, 4: 70–78.
- Hollan, D.W. and C.J. Throop, 2008, “Whatever Happened to Empathy? Introduction”, Ethos, 36: 385–401.
- –––, 2011, The Anthropology of Empathy: Experiencing the Lives of Others in Pacific Societies, New York: Berghahn Books.
- Holz-Ebeling, F. and M. Steinmetz, 1995, “Wie brauchbar sind die vorliegenden Fragebogen zur Messung von Empathie? Kritische Analysen unter Berücksichtigung der Iteminhalte”, Zeitschrift für Differentielle und Diagnostische Psychologie, 16: 11–32.
- Hume, D., 1739–40 [1978], A Treatise of Human Nature, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 1748 [1983]., An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, Indianapolis: Hackett.
- Husserl, E., 1931 [1963], Cartesianische Meditationen und Pariser Vorträge, Gesammelte Werke, vol. 1. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1963; translated as Cartesian Meditations, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
- Hutto, D., 2008, Folk-Psychological Narratives, The Sociocultural Basis of Understanding Reasons, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Iacoboni, M., 2011, “Within Each Other: Neural Mechanisms for Empathy in the Primate Brain”, in A. Coplan and P. Goldie (eds.), Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 45–57.
- Ickes, W., 1993, “Empathic Accuracy”, Journal of Personality, 61: 587–610.
- –––(ed.), 1997, Empathic Accuracy, New York/London: Guilford Press.
- –––, 2003, Everyday Mindreading, New York. Prometheus Book.
- Jackson, F., 1982, “Epiphenomenal Qualia”, Philosophical Quarterly, 32(127): 126–136.
- Jacob, P., 2008, “What Do Mirror Neurons Contribute to Human Social Cognition?”, Mind and Language, 23: 190–223.
- –––, 2011, “The Direct–Perception Model of Empathy: A Critique”, Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2: 519–540.
- Johnson, J., J. Cheek, and R. Smither, 1983, “The Structure of Empathy,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 45: 1299–1312.
- Jolliffe, D., and D.P. Farrington, 2006. “Development and Validation of the Basic Empathy Scale”, Journal of Adolescence, 29: 589–611.
- Jordon, R., Amir, D., and P. Bloom, 2016, “Are Empathy and Concern Psychologically Distinct?”, Emotion, 16: 1107–1116.
- Kain, W. and J. Perner, 2003, “Do children with ADHD not need their frontal lobes for theory of mind?: A review of brain imaging and neuropsychological studies”, in M. Brüne, H. Ribbert, and W. Schiefenhövel (eds.), The Social Brain: Evolution and Pathology, Chichester, UK: John Wiley, pp. 197–230.
- Kauppinen, A., 2014, “Empathy, Emotion Regulation, and Moral Judgment”, in H. Maibom (ed.), Empathy and Morality, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 97–121.
- –––, 2017a, “Empathy and Moral Judgment”, in H. Maibom (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Empathy, New York: Routledge, 215–226.
- –––, 2017b, “Sentimentalism, Blameworthiness, and Wrongdoing”, in R. Debes and K. Stueber (eds.), Ethical Sentimentalism: New Perspectives, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp.133–152.
- Keen, S., 2007, Empathy and the Novel, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Kelly, D., S. Stich, K. Haley, S. Eng, and D. Fessler, 2007, “Harm, Affect, and the Moral/Conventional Distinction”, Mind and Language, 22: 117–131.
- Kennett, J., 2002, “Autism, Empathy and Moral Agency”, The Philosophical Quarterly, 50: 340–357.
- –––, 2011, “Imagining Reasons”, Southern Journal of Philosophy (Supplementary Volume), 49: 181–192.
- Keysers, C., 2011, The Empathic Brain: How the Discovery of Mirror Neurons Changes our Understanding of Human Nature, Kindle E-book and Createspace Independent Publishing Platform.
- Kim, J., 1984, “Self-Understanding and Rationalizing Explanations”, Philosophia Naturalis, 21: 309–320.
- –––, 1998, “Reasons and the First Person,” in J. Bransen and St. Cuypers (eds.), Human Action, Deliberation, and Causation, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 67–87.
- Kind, A., 2020, “What Imagination Teaches”, in E. Lambert and J. Schwenkler (eds.), Becoming Someone New: Essays on Transformative Experience, Choice, and Change, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 133–146.
- Kögler, H.-H., and K. Stueber, 2000. Empathy and Agency: The Problem of Understanding in the Human Sciences, Boulder: Westview Press.
- Krause, S.R., 2008, Civil Passions: Moral Sentiments and Democratic Deliberation, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
- –––, 2011, “Empathy, Democratic Politics, and the Impartial Juror, Law, Culture and the Humanities”, 7(1): 81–100.
- Kteily, N. and E. Bruneau, 2017, “Darker Demons of Our Nature: The Need to (Re-)Focus Attention on Blatant Forms of Dehumanization”, Current Directions in Psychological Science, 26: 487–494.
- Lavelle, J.S., 2019, The Social Mind: A Philosophical Introduction. London: Routledge.
- Lamm, C., D. D. Batson, and J. Decety, 2007, “The Neural Substrate of Human Empathy: Effects of Perspective-Taking and Cognitive Appraisal”, Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 19: 42–58.
- Lanzoni, S., 2018, Empathy: A History, New Haven: Yale University Press.
- Leslie, A.M., R. Mallon, and J.A. DiCorcia, 2006, “Transgressors, Victims, and Cry Babies: Is Basic Moral Judgment Spared in Autism?”, Social Neuroscience, 1: 270–283.
- Lipps, T., 1903a, “Einfühlung, Innere Nachahmung und Organempfindung”, Archiv für gesamte Psychologie 1: 465–519; translated as “Empathy, Inner Imitation and Sense-Feelings,” in A Modern Book of Esthetics, 374–382. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1979.
- –––, 1903b, Aesthetik (Volume 1), Hamburg: Voss Verlag.
- –––, 1905, Aesthetik (Volume 2), Hamburg: Voss Verlag.
- –––, 1906, “Einfühlung und Ästhetischer Genuß”, Die Zukunft, 16: 100–114.
- –––, 1907, “Das Wissen von Fremden Ichen”, Psychologische Untersuchungen, 1: 694–722.
- –––, 1912/13, “Zur Einfühlung,” Psychologische Untersuchungen, 2: 111–491.
- MacKenzie, C. and S. Sorial, 2022, “The Empathy Dilemma: Democratic Deliberation, Epistemic Injustice, and the Problem of Empathic Imagination”, Res Publica, 28: 365–389.
- Maibom, H., 2005, “Moral Unreason: The Case of Psychopathy,” Mind and Language, 20: 237–257.
- –––, 2007, “The Presence of Others”, Philosophical Studies, 132: 161–190.
- –––, 2009, “Feeling for Others: Empathy, Sympathy, and Morality”, Inquiry, 52: 483–499.
- ––– (ed.), 2014, Morality and Empathy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2017, “Psychopathy: Morally Incapacitated Persons”, in Th. Schramme and S. Edwards (eds.), Handbook of the Philosophy of Medicine, Berlin/New York: Springer, pp. 1131–1144.
- –––, 2022, The Space Between: How Empathy Really Works, New York: Oxford University Press
- Makkreel, R., 2000. “From Simulation to Structural Transposition: A Diltheyan Critique of Empathy and Defense of Verstehen”, in H.H. Kögler and K. Stueber (eds.), Empathy and Agency: The Problem of Understanding in the Human Sciences, Boulder: Westview Press, pp. 181–193.
- Marsh, A., 2014. “Empathy and Moral Deficits in Psychopaths,” in Empathy and Morality, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 138–154.
- Matravers, D., 2018, “ The Object of Empathic Emotions,” in D. Matravers and A. Waldow (eds.), Philosophical Perspectives on Empathy: Theoretical Approaches and Empirical Challenges, New York: Routledge, 60–73.
- May, J., 2018, Regard for Reason in the Moral Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- May, L., M. Friedman, and A. Clark, 1996, Mind and Morals, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- McGeer, V., 2008, “Varieties of Moral Agency: Lessons from Autism,” in W. Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.), Moral Psychology (Volume 3), Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 227–248.
- Mead. G.H., 1934, Mind, Self, and Society, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Mehrabian, A., and N. Epstein, 1972, “A Measure of Emotional Empathy”, Journal of Personality, 40: 525–543.
- Mehrabian, A., A.L. Young, and S. Sato, 1988, “Emotional Empathy and Associated Individual Differences”, Current Psychology: Research and Review, 7: 221–240.
- Meltzoff, A., and R. Brooks, 2001. “‘Like Me’ as a Building Block for Understanding Other Minds: Bodily Acts, Attention, and Intention,” in B. Malle, L. Moses, and D. Baldwin (eds.), Intentions and Intentionality, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 171–191.
- Meyers, D. T. 2017, “A Modest Feminist Sentimentalism: Empathy and Moral Understanding Across Social Difference”, in R. Debes and K. Stueber (eds.), Ethical Sentimentalism: New Perspectives, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 210–229.
- Morrell, M., 2010, Empathy and Democracy: Feeling, Thinking and Deliberation, University Park: Penn State University Press.
- Nichols, S., 2001, “Mindreading and the Cognitive Architecture underlying Altruistic Motivation”, Mind & Language, 16: 425–455.
- –––, 2004, Sentimental Rules: On the Natural Foundation of Moral Judgment, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Nagel, T., 1974, “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?”, Philosophical Review, 83(4): 435–450.
- Nichols, S., and S. Stich, 2003, Mindreading, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Neuberg, S.L., R. Cialdini, S.L. Brown, C. Luce, and B. Sagarin, 1997, “Does Empathy Lead to Anything More Than Superficial Helping?”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 73: 510–516.
- Nussbaum, M., 2001, Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Oxley, J.C., 2011, The Moral Dimensions of Empathy: Limits and Applications in Ethical Theory and Practice, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
- Paul, L.A. 2014, Transformative Experience, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2020, “Who Will I Become”, in E. Lambert and J. Schwenkler (eds.), Becoming Someone New: Essays on Transformative Experiences, Choice, and Change, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 16–36.
- Persson, I., and J. Savulescu, 2018, “The Moral Importance of Reflective Empathy”, Neuroethics, 11: 183–193.
- Petraschka, T. and C. Werner, 2024, Empathy’s Role in Understanding Persons, Literature, and Art, London and New York: Routledge.
- Prandl, A., 1910, Die Einfühlung, Leipzig: Verlag von Johann Ambrosius Barth.
- Preston, S., and F. de Waal, 2002a, “Empathy: Its Ultimate and Proximate Bases”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 25: 1–72.
- –––, 2002b, “Communications of Emotions and the Possibility of Empathy in Animals”, in S. Post, L. Underwood, J. Schloss, and W. Hurblut (eds.), Altruism and Altruistic Love: Science, Philosophy, and Religion in Dialogue, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 284–308.
- Prinz, J., 2011a, “Is Empathy Necessary for Morality?” in A. Coplan and P. Goldie (eds.), Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 211–229.
- –––, 2011b, “Against Empathy”, The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 49 (Spindel Supplement): 214–233.
- Ravenscroft, I., 1998, “What is it Like to be Someone Else? Simulation and Empathy”, Ratio, 11: 170–185.
- Read, H., 2021, “Empathy and Common Ground”, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 24: 1–15.
- –––, 2022, “When and Why to Empathize with Political Opponents”, Philosophical Studies, 180(3): 773–793.
- Rhodes, M. and L. Chalik, 2013, “Social Categories as Markers of Intrinsic Interpersonal Obligations”, Psychological Science, 26: 999–1006.
- Rifkin, J., 2009, The Empathic Civilization: The Race to Global Consciousness in a World in Crisis, New York: Tarcher/Penguin.
- Rizzolatti, G., and L. Craighero, 2004, “The Mirror Neuron System”, Annual Review Neuroscience, 27: 169–192.
- Rizzolatti, G. and C. Sinigaglia, 2008, Mirrors in the Brain: How our Minds Share Actions and Emotions, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 2016, “The Mirror Mechanism: A Basic Principle of Brain Function,” Nature Review Neuroscience, 17: 757–765.
- Rogers, C., 1959, “A Theory of Therapy, Personality, and Interpersonal Relations, as Developed in the Client-Centered Framework”, in S. Koch (ed.), Psychology: A Study of a Science (Volume 3), New York: McGraw–Hill, pp. 184–256.
- –––, 1975, “Empathic: An Unappreciated Way of Being”, The Counseling Psychologist, 5: 2–10 (Reprinted in C. Rogers. 1980. A Way of Being, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 137–164.
- Roughley, N., 2018, “The Empathy in Moral Obligation: An Exercise in Creature Construction”, in N. Roughley and T. Schramme (eds.), Forms of Fellow Feeling: Empathy, Sympathy and Moral Agency, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 265–291.
- Sayre-McCord, G., 1994, “On Why Hume’s ‘General Point of View’ Isn’t Ideal—And Shouldn’t Be”, Social Philosophy and Policy, 11: 202–228.
- –––, 2013, “Hume and Smith on Sympathy, Approbation, and Moral Judgment”, Social Philosophy and Policy, 30: 208–236.
- Sherman, N., 1998, “Empathy and Imagination”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 22: 82–119.
- Seemann, A., 2011, Joint Attention: New Developments in Psychology, Philosophy of Mind, and Social Neuroscience, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Scheler, M., 1973, Wesen und Form der Sympathie, Bern/München: Francke Verlag; English translation, The Nature of Sympathy, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul 1954.
- Schleiermacher, Fr., 1998. Hermeneutics and Criticism, edited by A. Bowie, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Schopenhauer, A., 1995. On the Basis of Morality, Providence: Berghahn Books.
- Simmons, A., 2014, “In Defense of the Moral Significance of Empathy”, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 17: 97–111.
- Singer, T., and C. Lamm, 2009, “The Social Neuroscience of Empathy,” The Year in Cognitive Neuroscience: Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1156, 81–96.
- Slote, M., 2007, The Ethics of Care and Empathy, London: Routledge.
- –––, 2010, Moral Sentimentalism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Smith, A., 1853, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, New York: August M. Kelley Publishers, 1966.
- Snow, N., 1991, “Compassion,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 28(3): 195–205.
- Sober, E. and D.S. Wilson, 1998, Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
- Song, Y., 2015, “How to be a Proponent of Empathy”, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 18: 437–451.
- Spaulding, S., 2017, “Cognitive Empathy”, in H. Maibom (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Empathy, London, Routledge, pp.22–32.
- –––, 2018, “Do You See What I See: How Social Differences Influence Mindreading”, Synthese, 195(9): 4009–4030.
- –––, 2024, “Motivating Empathy”, Mind and Language, 39(2): 220–236.
- Spinrad, T.L. and N.Eisenberg, 2014, “Empathy and Morality: A Developmental Psychology Perspective”, in H. Maibom (ed.), Empathy and Morality, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 59–70.
- Stein, E., 1917, Zum Problem der Einfühlung, München: Kaffke Verlag, 1980; English translation, E. Stein, On the Problem of Empathy, Washington: ICS Publishers, 1989.
- Stotland, E., 1969, “Exploratory Investigations of Empathy”, Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, (Vol. 4), L. Berkowitz (ed.), New York/London: Academic Press, 271–314.
- Stueber, K., 2006, Rediscovering Empathy: Agency, Folk Psychology, and the Human Sciences, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- –––, 2008, “Reasons, Generalizations, Empathy, and Narratives: The Epistemic Structure of Action Explanation”, History and Theory, 47: 31–43.
- –––, 2011, “Social Cognition and the Allure of the Second-Person Perspective: In Defense of Empathy and Simulation”, in A. Seemann (ed.), Joint Attention: New Developments in Psychology, Philosophy of Mind, and Social Neuroscience, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 265–292.
- –––, 2012a, “Varieties of Empathy, Neuroscience and the Narrativist Challenge to the Theory of Mind Debate,” Emotion Review, 4: 55–63.
- –––, 2012b, “Understanding versus Explanation: How to Think about the Distinction between the Human and the Natural Sciences”, Inquiry, 55: 17–32.
- –––, 2017, “Smithian Constructivism: Elucidating the Reality of the Normative Domain,” in R. Debes and K. Stueber (eds.), Ethical Sentimentalism: New Perspectives, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, pp. 192–209.
- –––, forthcoming, “Empathy, Imaginative Resistance, and Fragmentary Understanding: Trying to Make Sense of Extremism”, in Rik Peels and Lorne Dawson (eds.), Explaining Extreme Beliefs: Theoretical, Methodological, and Ethical Challenges (Extreme Belief and Behavior Series: Volume 3), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Taft, R., 1955, “The Ability to Judge People”, Psychological Bulletin, 52: 1–23.
- Titchener, E. B., 1909, Lectures on the Experimental Psychology of Thought-Processes, New York: Macmillan.
- Tully, J. (ed.), 1988. Meaning and Context: Quentin Skinner and his Critics, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
- Turiel, E., 1983, The Development of Social Knowledge: Morality and Convention, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Throop, C.J., 2010, “Latitudes of Loss: On the Vicissitudes of Empathy”, American Ethnologist, 37: 771–782.
- Vendrall Ferran, I., 2025. “Can We Empathize With Emotions That We Never Felt”, in Vendrall Ferran, I. and C. Werner (eds.), Imagination and Experience: Philosophical Explorations, London and New York: Routledge, pp. 232–252.
- Vendrall Ferran, I. and C. Werner (eds.), 2025, Imagination and Experience: Philosophical Explorations, London and New York: Routledge.
- Vischer, R., 1873, “On the Optical Sense of Form: A Contribution to Aesthetics,” in Empathy, Form, and Space, in H.F. Mallgrave and Eleftherios Ikonomou (eds., trans.), Santa Monica, CA: The Getty Center for the History of Art and the Humanities, 1994, 89–123.
- Werner, C. 2023, “Concurring Emotions, Empathy, and Phenomenal Understanding”, Passion: Journal of the European Society for the Study of Emotions, 1(2): 108–124.
- –––, 2024, “Empathic Scaffolding: How Literary Ways of Writing About Experiences Improve Readers’ Empathy”, Texas Studies in Literature and Language, 66(4): 399–421.
- Wiltsher, N., 2021, “Understanding What It’s Like to Be (Dis)Priviliged”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 102: 320–356.
- Winch, P., 1958, The Idea of a Social Science and its Relation to Philosophy, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- Wispe, L., 1986, “The Distinction between Sympathy and Empathy: To Call Forth a Concept a Word is Needed,” in Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 50: 314–321.
- –––, 1987, “History of the Concept of Empathy”, in N. Eisenberg and J. Strayer (eds.), Empathy and Its Development, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 17–37.
- –––, 1991, The Psychology of Sympathy, New York/London: Plenum Press.
- Xu, X., X. Zuo, X. Wang, and S. Han, 2009, “Do You Feel My Pain? Racial Group Membership Modulates Empathic Neural Responses”, Journal of Neuroscience, 29: 8525–8529,
- Zahavi, D., 2001, “Beyond Empathy: Phenomenological Approaches to Intersubjectivity”, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8: 151–167.
- –––, 2005, Subjectivity and Selfhood: Investigating the First-Person Perspective, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- –––, 2010, “Empathy, Embodiment and Interpersonal Understanding: From Lipps to Schutz”, Inquiry, 53: 285–306.
- Zahavi, D., and S. Overgaard, 2012, “Empathy without Isomorphism: A Phenomenological Account”, in J. Decety (ed.), Empathy: From Bench to Bedside, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 3–20.
- Zaki, J., 2014. “Empathy: A Motivated Account”, Psychological Bulletin, 140: 1608–1647.
- Zaki, J. and K. Ochsner, 2012, in J. Decety (ed.), “The Cognitive Neuroscience of Sharing and Understanding Others’ Emotions”, in Empathy: From Bench to Bedside, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 207–226.
- Zalla, T., L. Barlassina, M. Buon, and M. Leboyer, 2011, “Moral Judgment in Adults with Autism Spectrum Disorders”, Cognition, 12: 115–126.
- Zhou, Q., C. Valiente, and N. Eisenberg, 2003., “Empathy and Its Measurement,” in S.J. Lopez and C.R. Snyder (eds.), Positive Psychological Assessment: A Handbook of Models and Measures, Washington, DC: American Psychological Association, pp. 269–284.
Additional Important Surveys of Empathy
- Maibom, H. (ed.), 2017. The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Empathy, New York: Routledge.
- Matraver, D., 2017. Empathy, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Academic Tools
How to cite this entry. Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society. Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.
Other Internet Resources
- Dictionary of the History of Ideas, maintained by The Electronic Text Center at the University of Virginia Library.