Holes

First published Thu Dec 5, 1996; substantive revision Mon May 12, 2025

Holes are an interesting case study for ontologists and epistemologists. On the one hand, naive descriptions of the world treat holes as objects of reference and quantification, on a par with ordinary material objects (‘This hole has no lid’; ‘That cheese has seven holes’). Moreover, we often appeal to holes to account for causal interactions (‘The hole in the roof caused a leak’), or to explain the occurrence of certain events (‘The water spilled because the bucket has a hole’). All this provides initial evidence for treating holes as real entities. On the other hand, holes appear to be much more elusive than ordinary objects, ontologically as well as epistemologically; after all, they are a paradigm example of nothingness. So one may wonder whether such evidence is to be taken seriously. Should we instead think that all talk about holes is a misleading façon de parler? Are holes real things, or are they mere entia representationis, as-if entities, fictions?

1. Problems

‘A hole?’ the rock chewer grunted. ‘No, not a hole’, said the will-o’-the-wisp despairingly. ‘A hole, after all, is something. This is nothing at all’. —Ende (1979/1983: 19)

Hole representations—no matter whether veridical—appear to be commonplace in human cognition. Not only do people have the impression of seeing holes; they also form a corresponding concept, which is normally lexicalised as a noun in ordinary languages. (Some languages even discriminate different types of hole, distinguishing e.g. between superficial hollows, inner cavities, and see-through perforations.) Moreover, data from developmental psychology and the psychology of perception confirm that infants and adults are able to perceive, count, and track holes just as easily as they perceive, count, and track paradigm material objects such as cookies and tins (Giralt & Bloom 2000; Horowitz & Kuzmova 2011; Porter et al. 2016). These facts do not prove that holes and material objects are on equal psychological footing, let alone on equal metaphysical footing. But they indicate that the concept of a hole is of significant salience in the common-sense picture of the world, specifically of the spatiotemporal world.

If holes are entities of a kind, then, they appear to be spatiotemporal particulars, like cookies and tins and unlike numbers or moral values. They appear to have a determinate shape, a size, and a location. (‘These things have birthplaces and histories. They can change, and things can happen to them’, Hofstadter & Dennett 1981: 6–7.) On the other hand, if holes are particulars, then they are not particulars of the familiar sort. For holes appear to be immaterial: every hole has a material “host” (the stuff around it, such as the edible part of a donut) and it may have a material “guest” (such as the liquid filling a cavity), but the hole itself does not seem to be made of matter. Indeed, holes seem to be made of nothing, if anything is. And this gives rise to a number of conundrums. For example:

  1. It is difficult to explain how holes can in fact be perceived. If perception is grounded on causation, as Locke urged (Essay, II-viii-6), and if causality has to do with materiality, then immaterial bodies cannot be the source of any causal flow. So a causal theory of perception would not apply to holes. Our impression of perceiving holes would then be a sort of systematic illusion, on pain of rejecting causal accounts of perception. (On the other hand, if one accepts that absences can be causally efficacious, as urged by Lewis 2004, then a causal account could maintain that we truly perceive holes; see Sorensen 2008 and 2015 along with Siegel 2009, Farennikova 2013, and Calabi 2019.)
  2. It is difficult to specify identity criteria for holes—more difficult than for ordinary material objects. If holes are immaterial, we cannot account for the identity of a hole via the identity of any constituting stuff. But neither can we rely on the identity conditions of the hole’s material host, for we can imagine changing the host—partly or wholly, gradually or abruptly—without affecting the hole. And we cannot rely on the identity conditions of its guest, for it would seem that we can empty a hole of whatever might partially or fully occupy it and leave the hole intact. (Indeed, both “host” and “guest” are relative notions. Doesn’t their proper application presuppose that we already know how to identify holes in the first place? See Meadows 2015.)
  3. It is equally difficult to account for the mereology of holes. Take a card and punch a hole in it. You have made one hole. Now punch again next to it. Have you made another hole? In a way, yes: now the card is doubly perforated. But what prevents us from saying that we still have one hole, though a hole that comes in two disconnected parts? After all, material objects can be disconnected: a bikini, your copy of the Recherche, a token of the lowercase letter ‘i’. Perhaps holes may be disconnected, too? If so, perhaps we have just punched a single, disconnected hole? (Casati & Varzi 2004, 2021)
  4. It is also difficult to assess the explanatory relevance of holes. Arguably, whenever a physical interaction can be explained by appealing to the concept of a hole, a matching explanation could be offered that invokes only material objects and their properties. (That the water ran out of the bucket can be explained by appealing to various facts about fluid dynamics, together with an accurate account of the physical and geometric conditions of the bucket.) Aren’t these latter explanations enough?

Further problems arise from the ambiguous status of holes in figure-ground displays. On the one hand, we have robust evidence that their perception is influenced by such factors as convexity (Arnheim 1948), contour relationship (Bozzi 1975), grouping (Nelson & Palmer 2001), or pattern entropy (Gillam & Grove 2011), and we understand how these factors relate to others, such as texture and shading (Bertamini & Helmy 2012). On the other hand, while it appears that the shapes of holes can be recognized by humans as accurately as the shapes of ordinary objects, the area seen through a hole typically belongs to the background of its host, and there is evidence to the effect that background regions are represented as shapeless (Rubin 1915). So what would the shape of a hole be, if any? (Bertamini & Croucher 2003; Palmer et al. 2008; Nelson et al. 2014; Bertamini & Casati 2015.)

2. Theories

These difficulties—along with some form of horror vacui—may lead a philosopher to favor ontological parsimony or revisionism over naive realism about holes. A number of options are available:

  1. One may hold that holes do not exist at all, arguing that all truths putatively about holes boil down to truths about holed objects (Jackson 1977: 132) or, more generally, that all sentences that seem to imply the existence of holes can be paraphrased by sentences that lack the implication but could in principle be used for all the same purposes as the original (van Inwagen 2014). This view calls for a systematic way of producing the relevant paraphrases. For instance, the sentence ‘There is a hole in the carpet’ can be treated as a mere grammatical variant of ‘The carpet is perforated’; the sentence ‘There are three round holes in that piece of cheese’ as a variant of ‘That piece of cheese is triply-roundly-holed’, etc. (Challenges: Can every quantification over holes be analyzed this way? Consider: ‘There are as many holes in my cheese as crackers on my plate’; Lewis & Lewis 1970: 207. Can a language be envisaged that contains all the necessary shape predicates? Consider: ‘There are two interlocking toroidal cavities in that piece of cheese’; Casati & Varzi 1994: 180. Can every hole-referring noun-phrase be de-nominalized? Consider: ‘The hole in the tooth was smaller than the dentist’s finest probe’; Geach 1968: 12.)
  2. One may hold that holes do exist, but they are nothing over and above the regions of spacetime at which they are found (Wake et al. 2007). Surely they are not just regions of space, for holes can move—as happens any time you move a donut—whereas regions of space cannot. However, as regions of spacetime, holes can be said to move in virtue of having different temporal parts follow one another in different places. (Challenges: Is this view compatible with a relationist metaphysics of spacetime? See Hestevold 2020, ch. 6. Is it compatible with the possibility that holes undergo rotational motion? Take the donut and spin it clockwise. Now take a wedding ring, put it inside the hole in the donut, and spin it counterclockwise. It would seem that the two holes are spinning in opposite directions. Since the relevant temporal part of the little hole is a spatiotemporal part of the bigger one, would it be spinning in both directions? See Lewis & Lewis 1970: 208.)
  3. One may hold instead that holes are qualified portions of spacetime (Miller 2007). There would be nothing peculiar about such portions as opposed to any others that we would not normally think of as being occupied by ordinary material objects, just as there would be nothing more problematic, in principle, in determining under what conditions a certain portion counts as a hole than there is in determining under what conditions it counts as a dog, a statue, or whatnot. (Challenge: What if there were truly unqualified portions of spacetime, in this or some other possible world? Would there be truly immaterial entities inhabiting such portions, and would holes be among them?)
  4. One might also hold that holes are ordinary material beings: they are neither more nor less than superficial parts of what, on the naive view, are their material hosts (Lewis & Lewis 1970; Mollica 2022). For every hole there is a hole-lining and for every hole-lining there is a hole; on this conception, the hole is the hole-lining. (Challenge: This calls for an account of the altered meaning of certain predicates or prepositions. Would holes surround themselves? Would filling a hole amount to filling space outside it? Would expanding the hole-lining amount to enlarging the hole?)
  5. Alternatively, one might hold that holes are parts of their material hosts, viz. “negative” parts (Hoffman & Richards 1985; Spröte & Fleming 2013). On this account, a donut would be a sort of hybrid mereological aggregate—the mereological sum of a positive pie and the negative bit in the middle. (Again, this calls for an account of the altered meaning of certain modes of speech. For instance, making a hole would amount to adding a part, and splitting a donut open would amount to removing a part, contrary to ordinary usage.)
  6. Yet another possibility is to treat holes as “disturbances” of some sort (Karmo 1977). On this view, a hole is always found in some object (its “medium”) in the same sense in which a knot may be found in a rope or a wrinkle in a carpet, and in each case the relevant in-relation would entail ontological dependence. (Linguistically, this feature of disturbances is naturally reflected in the corresponding have-constructions: ‘The cheese has a hole’, ‘The rope has a knot’, ‘The carpet has a wrinkle’; see Moltmann 2019. Metaphysically, however, the status of disturbances calls for refinements. Simons 1987: 308 suggests construing them as Husserlian moments that continuously change their fundaments, but this seems to suit knots and wrinkles better than holes.)
  7. Finally, it may be held that holes are not the particulars they seem to be. Perhaps they are properties, viz. spatial qualities of their owners (O’Shaughnessy 2000: 333), or ways things are (Meadows 2013), or relational entities whose fundamental mode of being is being-in (McDaniel 2010). Perhaps holes are ways the world is, viz. non-abstract, localized absences that can serve as truth-makers for negative existentials or false-makers for positive existentials (Martin 1996). Or perhaps holes are genuine negative facts, viz. anti-instantiations of material properties by material things: an absence of F-stuff constitutes a hole insofar as it is surrounded by the presence of F-stuff (Barker & Jago 2012).

On the other hand, the possibility remains of taking holes at face value, which is to say as bona fide immaterial particulars. Any such undertaking would have to account, not only for the general features mentioned in section 1, but also for a number of additional peculiarities (Casati & Varzi 1994). Among others:

  1. Holes are ontologically parasitic: they are always in something and cannot exist in isolation. (‘There is no such thing as a hole by itself’, Tucholsky 1931: 100; ‘Take away the thing, and the hole goes too’, Heath 1967: 524). This is why there cannot exist a world consisting only of holes (Coggins 2010: 71).
  2. Holes are fillable. You don’t necessarily destroy a hole by filling it up (except perhaps when the filling is homogeneous with the hole-lining); you don’t create a new hole by removing the filling.
  3. Holes are locationally gracious. When you fill or put something in a hole, the hole does not squeeze to the side; it shares its location with its guest (and if the guest has a hole, you get two co-located entities of the same kind).
  4. Holes are mereologically structured. They have parts and can bear part-whole relations to one another (though not to their hosts and not to their guests).
  5. Holes are topologically assorted. Superficial hollows are distinguished from internal cavities; straight perforations are distinguished from knotted tunnels.

As is often the case, the choice between all these alternatives—whether holes are to be subjected to Ockham’s razor, reduced to other entities, or taken at face value—will depend on one’s general metaphysical inclinations (Lewis & Lewis 1996). It may also depend on controversial details concerning the nature of space and spacetime, e.g. whether they are relational or substantival (Braddon-Mitchell & Miller 2015). It is, more generally, an instance of the sort of decision philosophers have to make when they scrutinize the ontology inherent in the common-sense picture of the world and the concepts, words, and purposes through which it is described and apprehended.

Bibliography

  • Arnheim, R., 1948, ‘The Holes of Henry Moore: On the Function of Space in Sculpture’, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 7: 29–38.
  • Barker, S., and Jago, M., 2012, ‘Being Positive About Negative Facts’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85: 117–138.
  • Bertamini, M., and Casati, R., 2015, ‘Figures and Holes’, in J. Wagemans (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Perceptual Organization, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 281–293.
  • Bertamini, M., and Croucher, C. J., 2003, ‘The Shape of Holes’, Cognition, 87: 33–54.
  • Bertamini, M., and Helmy, M. S., 2012, ‘The Shape of a Hole and that of the Surface-with-hole Cannot be Analysed Separately’, Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 19: 608–616.
  • Bozzi, P., 1975, ‘Osservazioni su alcuni casi di trasparenza fenomica realizzabili con figure a tratto’, in G. B. Flores d’Arcais (ed.), Studies in Perception: Festschrift for Fabio Metelli, Milan/Florence: Martelli-Giunti, pp. 88–110; English translation by R. Davies and I. Bianchi: ‘Observations on Some Cases of Phenomenal Transparency Obtained with Line Drawings’, in I. Bianchi and R. Davies (eds.), Paolo Bozzi’s Experimental Phenomenology, London: Routledge, 2019, pp. 305–321.
  • Braddon-Mitchell, D., and Miller, K., 2015 ‘On Metaphysical Analysis’, in B. Loewer and J. Schaffer (eds.), A Companion to David Lewis, London: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 40–59.
  • Calabi, C., 2019, ‘The Eye of the Needle: Seeing Holes’, in R. Davies (ed.), Natural and Artifactual Objects in Contemporary Metaphysics, London: Bloomsbury, pp. 93–102.
  • Casati, R., and Varzi, A. C., 1994, Holes and Other Superficialities, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2004, ‘Counting the Holes’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82: 23–27.
  • –––, 2021, ‘Ballot Ontology’, in S. Bernstein and T. Goldschmidt (eds.), Non-Being: New Essay on the Metaphysics of Non-Existence, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 139–164.
  • Coggins, G., 2010, Could There Have Been Nothing?, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
  • Ende, M., 1979, Die unendliche Geschichte: von A bis Z, Stuttgart: Thienemann. English translation by R. Manheim: The Neverending Story, Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1983.
  • Farennikova, A., 2013, ‘Seeing Absence’, Philosophical Studies, 166: 429–454.
  • Geach, P., 1968, ‘What Actually Exists’, Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 42: 7–16.
  • Gillam, B., and Grove, P. M., 2011, ‘Contour Entropy: A New Determinant of Perceiving Ground or a Hole’, Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 37: 750–757.
  • Giralt, N., and Bloom, P., 2000, ‘How Special Are Objects? Children’s Reasoning about Objects, Parts, and Holes’, Psychological Science, 11: 503–507.
  • Heath, P. L., 1967, ‘Nothing’, in P. Edwards (ed.), The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Volume 5), London: Macmillan, pp. 524–525.
  • Hestevold, H. S., 2020, Toward a Directionalist Theory of Space: On Going Nowhere, Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
  • Hoffman, D. D., and Richards, W. A., 1985, ‘Parts of Recognition’, Cognition, 18: 65–96.
  • Hofstadter, D. R., and Dennett, D. C., 1981, The Mind’s I. Fantasies and Reflections on Self and Soul, New York: Basic Books.
  • Horowitz, T., and Kuzmova, Y., 2011, ‘Can We Track Holes?’, Vision Research, 51: 1013–1021.
  • Jackson, F., 1977, Perception. A Representative Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Karmo, T., 1977, ‘Disturbances’, Analysis, 37: 147–148.
  • Lewis, D. K., 2004, ‘Void and Object’, in J. D. Collins, N. Hall, and L. A. Paul (eds.), Causation and Counterfactuals, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 277–290.
  • Lewis, D. K., and Lewis, S. R., 1970, ‘Holes’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 48: 206–212.
  • –––, 1996, Review of Casati and Varzi 1994, The Philosophical Review, 105: 77–79.
  • Martin, C. B., 1996, ‘How It Is: Entities, Absences and Voids’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74: 57–65.
  • McDaniel, K., 2010, ‘Being and Almost Nothingness’, Noûs, 44: 628–649.
  • Meadows, P. J., 2013, ‘What Angles Can Tell Us About What Holes Are Not’, Erkenntnis, 78: 319–331.
  • –––, 2015, ‘Holes Cannot Be Counted as Immaterial Objects’, Erkenntnis, 80: 841–852.
  • Miller, K., 2007, ‘Immaterial Beings’, The Monist, 90: 349–371.
  • Mollica, L., 2022, ‘Argle Victorious: A Theory of Holes as Hole-Linings’, Synthese, 200 (457). doi:10.1007/s11229-022-03952-z
  • Moltmann, F., 2019, ‘Ontological Dependence, Spatial Location, and Part Structure’, in S. Borgo et al. (eds.), Ontology Makes Sense: Essays in Honor of Nicola Guarino, Amsterdam: IOS Press, pp. 211–220.
  • Nelson, R., and Palmer, S. E., 2001, ‘Of Holes and Wholes: The Perception of Surrounded Regions’, Perception, 30: 1213–1226.
  • Nelson, R., Reiss, J. E., Gong, X., Conklin, S., Parker, L., and Palmer, S. E., 2014, ‘The Shape of a Hole is Perceived as the Shape of its Interior’, Perception, 43: 1033–1048.
  • O’Shaughnessy, B., 2000, Consciousness and the World, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Palmer, S. E., Davis, J., Nelson, R., and Rock, I., 2008, ‘Figure-Ground Effects on Shape Memory for Objects versus Holes’, Perception, 37: 1569–1586.
  • Porter, K. B., Mazza, V., Garofalo, A., and Caramazza, A., 2016, ‘Visual Object Individuation Occurs over Object Wholes, Parts, and Even Holes’, Attention, Perception & Psychophysics, 78: 1145–1162.
  • Rubin, E., 1915, Synsoplevede figurer: Studier i psykologisk analyse, Gyldendal: Nordisk; Abridged English translation by M. Wertheimer: ‘Figure and Ground’, in D. C. Beardslee and M. Wertheimer (eds.), Readings in Perception, Princeton, NJ: Van Nostrand, 1958, pp. 194–203.
  • Siegel, S., 2009, ‘The Visual Experience of Causation’, The Philosophical Quarterly, 59: 519–540.
  • Simons, P. M., 1987, Parts. A Study in Ontology, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Sorensen, R., 2008, Seeing Dark Things. The Philosophy of Shadows, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2015, ‘Perceiving Nothings’, in M. Matthen (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Perception, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 542–563
  • Spröte, P., and Fleming, R. W., 2013, ‘Concavities, Negative Parts, and the Perception that Shapes Are Complete’, Journal of Vision, 13(14). doi:10.1167/13.14.3
  • Tucholsky, K., 1931, ‘Zur soziologischen Psychologie der Löcher’ (signed Kaspar Hauser), Die Weltbühne, March 17, p. 389; reprinted in K. Tucholsky, Gesammelte Werke (ed. by M. Gerold-Tucholsky and F. J. Raddatz), Reinbek: Rowohlt Verlag, 1960, Vol. 3, pp. 804–805; English translation by H. Zohn: ‘The Social Psychology of Holes’, in H. Zohn (ed.), Germany? Germany! The Kurt Tucholsky Reader, Manchester: Carcanet Press, 1990, pp. 100–101.
  • van Inwagen, P., 2014, ‘Alston on Ontological Commitment’, in his Existence. Essays in Ontology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 137–152.
  • Wake, A., Spencer, J., and Fowler, G., 2007, ‘Holes as Regions of Spacetime’, The Monist, 90: 372–378.

Other Internet Resources

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

Copyright © 2025 by
Roberto Casati <casati@ehess.fr>
Achille Varzi <achille.varzi@columbia.edu>

Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative.
The Encyclopedia Now Needs Your Support
Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free