Ikhwān al-Safā’
The Ikhwān al-Safā’ or “Brethren of Purity”, as their name is commonly translated, are the authors of one of the most complete Medieval encyclopedias of sciences, antecedent at least two centuries to the best known in the Latin world (by Alexander Neckham, Thomas de Cantimpré, Vincent de Beauvais, Bartholomaeus Anglicus, all dating back to the 13th century). The “encyclopedia” is a collection of Epistles, the Arabic title of which is Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’ wa Khullān al-Wafā’ (Epistles of the Pure Brethren and the Sincere Friends). It consists of extremely heterogeneous materials, reworked to represent the whole educational training intended for an élite (see later). It is very well known, and a great deal of research into it has been done by Eastern and Western scholars, but the variety of topics addressed and the questions raised as to the identity and ideology of its authors remain unsolved. In an isolated form, and under a false attribution, some of these treatises came to the Latin Middle Ages through the Spanish version by Maslama al-Majrītī, which is traditionally placed at the beginnings of the 11th century. This already discussed chronology (Carusi 2000, 494–500) is recently questioned by several scholars. The development of research in this direction was encouraged by the pioneer study, Fierro 1996, part. 94 and 106–108; cf. also Hamdani 1978, 350; Hamdani, Soufan 2019, 11–12 (see infra).
- 1. Authorship
- 2. Naming and dating
- 3. Ideological commitment
- 4. The extant corpus
- 5. The classical heritage
- 6. The religious component
- Bibliography
- Academic Tools
- Other Internet Resources
- Related Entries
1. Authorship
The authors introduce themselves as a kind of “brotherhood” (maʿāshara) of sages. Their work is addressed to “beginners,” who may thereby increase their knowledge. The literary scholar Abū Hayyān al-Tawhīdī (922–32/1023), basing his work on the ideas of his master Abū Sulaymān al-Mantiqī (c. 912/c. 985), and the Muʿtazili theologian ʿAbd al-Jabbār al-Hamadānī (c. 936/1025) have identified the names of these authors. They are understood to be the qādī Abū’l-Hasan ʿAlī b. Hārūn al-Zanjānī and his three friends, Abū Sulaymān Muhammad b. Maʿshar al-Bustī, called al-Maqdisī, Abū Ahmad al-Nahrajūrī and al-ʿAwfī. All of these men came from Basra and were linked to the Chancellery secretary Zayd b. Rifāʿa (cf. Stern, 1946; Stern, 1964). The text of al-Tawhīdī is accurately examined in Kraemer 1986, 136, 230 ff. This authorship is now questioned by several scholars, because the learned who transmitted the Epistles to al-Andalus appears to be Maslama al-Qurtubī al-Majrītī, not later than the first half of the 10th century.
2. Naming and dating
With regard to the common denomination of “Ikhwān al-Safā’,” the old hypothesis by I. Goldziher deserves mention: according to which the name could have been borrowed from the famous collection of fables of indo-persian origin Kalīla wa Dimna to indicate a group of loyal friends. However, Stern (1964, 421) considers the name to be a hint at an idealised, utopian Ismāʿīlī movement that pursues the salvation of souls through the philosophically enlightened beliefs expounded in the Epistles. The most convincing hypothesis seems to be that which links the name to the content and goals of the encyclopedia – the salvation of soul through attainment of knowledge and purification of heart (Diwald 1975, 16–22). Recently, Poonawala hypothesized “Ikhwān al-Safā’” to be a pseudonym hiding the identity of the authors (Poonawala 2015a, 264 and 272).
As to the date, in the 19th century F. Dieterici proposed 961 to 986, basing his estimate on the work of the seventeenth century lexicographer Hājjī Khalīfa and on the presence in the treatises of verses by the famous poet al-Mutanabbī (d. 965). Massignon (1913) used a verse by the poet Ibn al-Rūmī (d. 896) to establish these years as the earliest possible date (cf. also Hamdani 1999, 76; Hamdani, Soufan 2019, 12; 28–29), and took the latest possible date to be the one indicated by the definition of sine (al-jayb) given by the Ikhwān. Such definition is not yet the one provided by al-Battānī (d. 929; reference to vol. I, p. 46 of the Bombay ed., 1887 –1889, corresponding to I, 86, 14–15 of the Beirut edition referred to in this article). The “expected event” frequently mentioned in the encyclopedia would then be the Fatimid conquest of Egypt, which can be traced back to those years. On the basis of astronomical data, Casanova (1915) moved the dates about a century forward, assigning the work to the years 1047–51.
Until some decades ago, the almost universally accepted dating was the one deduced from the testimonies of al-Tawhīdī and ʿAbd al-Jabbār al-Hamadānī (see above, 1. Authorship). Marquet reconfirmed Dieterici’s earlier hypothesis, placing the compilation of the work between 961 and 980 (al-Tawhīdī’s testimony is dated 981), but he also brought the date back to 909, depending on the hypothesis of an Ismāʿīlī affiliation of the authors. Two treatises have given rise to the idea of an Ismāʿīlī interpretation: Epistle 48 On the invitation (daʿwa) to God and Epistle 50 On the kinds of administration. The encyclopedia would therefore be the oldest exposition of the Ismāʿīlī doctrine, and consequently, the “expected event” might have been the proclamation of the Fatimid caliph ʿAbd Allāh al-Mahdī in Ifrīqiya, which happened in that year (Marquet 1981, 95; Marquet 1972, 66). Abbas Hamdani, an Ismāʿīlī scholar, summarizes various opinions concerning the dates of the encyclopedia, and establishes that it was composed in its whole between 873 and 909 (Hamdani 1978; Hamdani 1999, 78; Hamdani 2008; Hamdani, Soufan 2019, 15–16; Poonawala sides with Hamdani’s chronology in Baffioni, Poonawala 2017, 307–308). Hamdani also thinks that the Ikhwān awaited the advent of the Fatimids, the Fatimid character of the Rasā’il not being in question (Hamdani 1979, 62); he configures a precise role of the imām in Epistle 48 (Hamdani, Soufan 2019, 6). The fourth section, apart from the first and the last treatises, is claimed to be the core around which the first three sections have been composed (Marquet 1998, 5), as well as the culmination of the epistles, which demonstrates the importance of the mystery of prophecy and of imamate (Marquet 1998, 8–9 and note 21). Also Madelung recently sided with the hypothesis of an Ismāʿīlism of the Ikhwān al-Safā’. Recalling that the Ismāʿīlis of Mashriq, Iraq and Iran did not recognize the claims of ʿAbd Allāh to be the expected imām, being rather committed to the Qarmat mission, Madelung hypothesizes that the Ismāʿīlis of Basra recognized as imām the member of the family who had remained hidden in Khurāsān, the same person who would also become the founder of the secret brotherhood of the Ihwān al-Safā’ (Madelung in print; but cf. De Smet 2017, 152, note 1). Madelung’s claim that the epistles are “under the auspices of the hidden seventh imam” is rejected by Poonawala, since “Muḥammad b. Ismāʿīl’s name is never mentioned in the Rasā’il” (Baffioni, Poonawala 2017, 303–305, also on the basis of Hamdani’s opinions).
A quite different chronology is proposed by de Callataÿ based on the astronomical cycles described in Epistle 36 On cycles and revolutions. He distinguishes three “medium conjunctions” of Saturn and Jupiter occurring every 240 years and a longer conjunction occurring approximately every 960 years. The year 571 (birth of the Prophet Muhammad) marks a “longest conjunction” (from Libra to Scorpio); the first “medium conjunction” in 809 is of no importance to the Ikhwān; the second (from Sagittarius to Capricorn) should take place in 1047, and would be the “imminent conjunction” described in Epistle 48; the third (from Capricorn to Aquarius) is awaited in 1286; and the “longest conjunction” (from Aquarius to Libra) will take place in 1524 and will correspond to the rising of the qā’im of the Resurrection (de Callataÿ 2005, 55–57; Walker et al. 2015, 150–152, 156, 204–206).
The authors of the encyclopedia have also been confined to a Muʿtazilite approach, or placed in an earlier age, under the Qarmat influence (Marquet 1977; Qarmats were the opponents of the Fatimid caliph ʿAbd Allāh al-Mahdī). So did Madelung many years ago; but considering his recent opinion, that the Rasā’il repudiate the Fatimids’ claim to the imamate on the basis of the fact that a new-born of eight months does not survive (that meaning that Muhammad ibn Ismāʿīl did not reach the Prophet’s rank; the relevant texts are studied in Baffioni 2016 and 2018), Poonawala wonders how he could ascribe the epistles to the Qarāmita, since this is a repudiation of the Qarāmita’s belief (Baffioni, Poonawala 2017, 305–307).
More recent studies, on the line of a seminal article by Fierro (Fierro Bello 1996; cf. Hamdani, Soufan 2019, 11–12, but also Carusi 2000), have identified Abū’l-Qāsim Maslama b. Qāsim al-Qurtubī, called al-Majrītī (d. 964, previously confused with the Spanish scientist and astronomer Maslama al-Majrītī, d. 1007) as the author of the encyclopedia (cf. Hamdani 1999, 75; de Callataÿ 2013, Kacimi 2014a, b, de Callataÿ, Moureau 2015). However, the one who introduced in Spain the whole work is still to be considered Abū’l-Ḥakam al-Kirmānī, d. 1066). Because of this new discovery, the timing of the Rasā’il has been anticipated of several decades at least. So, the old attribution of al-Tawhīdī and ʿAbd al-Jabbār was revoked in doubt, beginning with de Callataÿ who had previously accepted it (de Callataÿ 2014; cf. Hamdani, Soufan 2019, 14–15; a reconstruction of the journey, material and intellectual, of Maslama al-Qurtubī in al-Andalus is in de Callataÿ, Moureau 2017). Maslama al-Qurtubī has been also recognized as the author of Rutbat al-hakīm (‘The level of the wise man’) and Ghāyat al-hakīm (‘The goal of the wise man’, being known in Latin as Picatrix), two important works on alchemy and magic respectively. These works were traditionally attributed to the scientist al-Majrītī, but are now believed to date from the first half of the 10th century. Scholars have also emphasized the impact of the encyclopedia on these two works, and it has even been hypothesized Maslama to be one of the authors of the epistles (Carusi 2000), which should not date later than 950. In the light of this new chronology, de Callataÿ 2014 examines the possible influence of the Ikhwān on the bātinī (‘esoterist’) thinker Ibn Masarra (d. 931), especially on his cosmology, reporting this author to the Andalusi bātinī context of the first half of the tenth century. If the epistles were circulating in al-Andalus already before 950, and their compilation must have begun some time before in the East, another consequence is that the Ikhwān influenced al-Fārābī and not vice versa, as it was believed so far (Hamdani 2011). According to Poonawala, the encyclopedia was composed after al-Kindī (d. between 864 and 870) but before al-Fārābī (d. 950; Poonawala 2011, Introduction, 59). It is said that Maslama b. Qāsim al-Qurtubī kept his identity secret while writing during the period when the followers of Ibn Masarra were persecuted by the Maliki jurists, who were the champions of the Umayyad caliphate’s orthodoxy in al-Andalus. In the Rutba, reference is made to certain Rasā’il. Fierro interprets this as an allusion to the encyclopedia, setting its latest possible date of completion at 936. At this time, Maslama was in Basra, where he may have encountered the encyclopedia’s authors. He would later introduce the epistles to al-Andalus. Carusi 2000 claims that Maslama considered the fifty-one epistles of the Brethren of Purity to be the basis for his own work. Kacimi 2014a, 33 believes that these epistles differ from those of the Ikhwān, despite the possibility of mutual influence or shared sources.
Later, Godefroid de Callataÿ (2013) reconsidered the issue and highlighted the ambiguity in Saʿīd al-Andalusī’s (d. 1070) account of how the Rasā’il were imported into al-Andalus by Abū’l-Hakam al-Kirmānī (d. 1066), who was a student of the scientist al-Majrītī. According to de Callataÿ, Tawhīdī’s testimony does not enable us to determine whether the individuals he mentions were the authors of the Rasā’il or merely the transmitters/compilers of an earlier, possibly much older version. De Callataÿ also recalls the hypothesis of Marquet 1978, who claimed that the final part of the corpus must have been written shortly before or after 909, the year that the Fatimid caliphate was founded in Ifrīqiya. Hamdani also claims that the epistles are an expression of pre-Fatimid Ismāʿīlism, composed between 873 and 909. De Callataÿ believes that Maslama “appropriated” the epistles while claiming not to be their author and placing them in a different time and context to his own. However, Maslama played a key role in copying and circulating the epistles in the Islamic West, long before the scholar al-Kirmānī, mentioned by Saʿīd al-Andalusī. De Callataÿ, on the other hand, considers Carusi’s suggestion that Maslama may have belonged to the Brotherhood in the East to be purely speculative (de Callataÿ 2013, 336). These ideas are taken up and further detailed in de Callataÿ, Moureau 2016. Among those who sustain the attribution of the epistles to Maslama al-Qurtubī is also Madelung who, therefore, rejects a too high dating of the epistles. The scholar has speculated that Maslama not only brought the encyclopedia to Spain, but also contributed to its composition: there would have been a first version, no longer existing, compiled not long before 937, the one described by al-Tawhīdī, and consisting of previously existing epistles and of epistles especially composed for the purpose; the Brotherhood would have been founded a few decades earlier (Madelung 2018, 404). Therefore, it can be assumed that the scientist al-Majrītī brought only a few treatises to al-Andalus, whereas his disciple al-Kirmānī was able to import them in their entirety (Kacimi 2014a, 39 and 41–43; Kacimi 2017, 743 and 745). He considers likely that the author of the Rutba might have belonged to the group of the Brethren of Purity, as proposed by Carusi (Kacimi, 2017, 748; Kacimi, 2014b, 43). This theory was also adopted by Madelung 2018, 406.
In recent times, al-Tawhīdī’s and ʿAbd al-Jabbār’s attribution has been reconsidered by emphasizing the Fatimid militancy of some among the pretended authors of the encyclopedia (Reymond 2011, 124–125). Hamdani recalls that, according to al-Tawhīdī, such personages were Qarmats, so that al-Tawhīdī could accuse of eresy Zayd b. Rifāʿa, too (Hamdani, Soufan 2019, 7–8, where the testimony of al-Qiftī is also discussed – that the alleged authors were followers of the imām ʿAlī). Hamdani even exploits al-Tawhīdī’s observation that the Rasā’il were widely read, as further evidence that they would have been written long before (cf. also de Vaulx d’Arcy 2019b). Kacimi (2014b, 31) thinks that, at the time of al-Tawhīdī, it was still difficult to have all the epistles available together. Poonawala shares historians’ doubts on al-Tawhīdī’s reliability and concludes that his one “is certainly a hostile witness” that implies the authors’ affiliation with the Qarāmita of Basra (Baffioni, Poonawala 2017, 294). Following Hamdani’s “deconstruction”, the witness is considered to be “very suspicious”, all the more so if one considers that most medieval authors and modern scholars are used to equate the Qarāmita with the Ismāʿīlis (Poonawala in Baffioni, Poonawala 2017, 298). Poonawala also emphasizes Stern’s remark on the qādī Abū’l-Hasan ʿAlī b. Hārūn al-Zanjānī – that ʿAbd al-Jabbār writes against the Ismāʿīlis without mentioning the Brethren at all (Baffioni, Poonawala 2017, 301–302).
De Callataÿ (2021) reconsidered the impact of the epistles on the Rutba and the Ghāya, basing his conclusions on textual evidence. In the Rutba, Maslama reveals far less familiarity with the encyclopedia — including the second version of the frequently quoted Epistle on Magic — than in the Ghāya. Therefore, contrary to his previous assumption, de Callataÿ hypothesizes that Maslama had no access to the Rasā’il before he began writing his last work. This once again indicates that Maslama was not the author of the epistles, but may have circulated them in Spain. The allusions to the Rasā’il in the Rutba suggest that Maslama wanted to convince his readers that studying his work would make approaching the Rasā’il unnecessary, which may also explain why he was ambiguous about their authorship. While writing the Ghāya, Maslama undoubtedly had a copy of the Rasā’il in front of him, although how he obtained it remains unclear. The reason he did not explicitly refer to the Rasā’il in the Ghāya may be that he “adopted the common practice of not explicitly acknowledging his debt to this notoriously unorthodox collection of writings stemming from the East” (De Callataÿ 2021, 509).
A new hypothesis on the real author of the Rasā’il has been formulated in Guillaume de Vaulx d’Arcy’s doctoral dissertation. The author tries to demonstrate that Ahmad b. al-Tayyib al-Sarakhsī, a pupil of al-Kindī, composed the whole encyclopedia in about 894 in the form in which we read it now (de Vaulx d’Arcy 2016, partially reelaborated in de Vaulx d’Arcy 2019a). The core of the author’s argument — that the encyclopedia has a predominantly mathematical value, revealed through its presumed author and helping us to reconstruct al-Kindī’s thinking on mathematics — was presented in de Vaulx d’Arcy 2019c. This time, the comparison is with an earlier version of Nicomachus’s Introduction to Arithmetic in relation to that of Thābit b. Qurra, which is attributed to Sarakhsī.
But the questions of the identity and ideology of the Ikhwān al-Safā’ still remain unsolved. Kacimi 2016 has come back to the relationship between the Ikhwān and the Sufi thought. Poonawala refuses them to have been Sufi, though some MSS, included the MS Atif Efendi 1618 (dated 1182, on which the new edition of the Institute of Ismaili Studies is based), bear in the title the mention of the Sufi school – or doctrines. Mayer thinks that to result from a later, Sunni manuscript tradition, “in which the acceptance, or at least toleration, of esoteric material was made likelier by presenting it as proper to Ṣūfī circles, whose respectability […] had been established by a figure of the magnitude of Ghazālī” (Traboulsi et al. 2016, 7).
The traces of classical thought in the encyclopedia, as well as their literary form, equally give an indication that the work was assembled in the course of several decades between the 9th and the first half of the 10th century, and that it may have undergone further elaborations. Such a collective enterprise can be considered as the result of a “stratified” compilation. The supposed reworking of the whole by members of the Brotherhood might also have shifted some Epistles from their original to their present place. Even the headings of the four sections of the encyclopedia are misleading. The way in which the treatises follow one another is often inconsistent. The authors must have planned a special use of the enormous amount of foreign philosophical and scientific knowledge that is explained in the treatises and to develop it in relation to the doctrinal conflicts and political changes that were occurring in their own times. In this sense the presentation of the encyclopedia as a “popular” work (Rudolph, 2004, 39) should be rejected.
3. Ideological commitment
Because their aim is clearly salvation, it has often been supposed that the Rasā’il were inspired by the Shīʿites, or perhaps even the Ismāʿīlis, both of whom claim the ideological commitment of the encyclopedia. For Marquet (1975, 585) the encyclopedia is the most ancient general exposition of the Ismāʿīlī doctrine. In 1150, the Sunni orthodoxy in the person of the caliph al-Mustanjid judged the work heretical and sent the existing versions to be burnt. Yet in spite of this, the encyclopedia survived and was translated into Persian and Turkish (Corbin, 1964, 193–194). A harsh judgment on the Ikhwān was delivered by the famous Mamlūk muftī and theologian Taqī al-Dīn Ahmad ibn Taymiyya (d. 1328). He considered them as Shīʿi esotericists whose doctrines contradict the religion of Islam. For this reason, he rejected the attribution of the Rasā’il to such an eminent religious scholar as Jaʿfar al-Sādiq (Michot 2008).
Attempts to define the Ikhwān’s ideological commitment have been made, but there has been no consensus on the matter. The Ikhwān’s view of ʿAlī as the Prophet’s legitimate legatee (walī) persuaded some scholars to link them to the Shīʿa, though scattered references in negative terms to the “hidden” imām appear contrary to twelver Shīʿism. Other elements have been alleged as proofs of the Ikhwān’s Ismāʿīlī inspiration, such as the hierarchical structure of universe, references to septenary cycles, distinction between elect and masses, the use of Ismāʿīlī symbols (e.g., the bee as symbol of the imām, etc.). Already Stanislas Guyard in 1874 published a fragment of the Ikhwān reporting it to Ismāʿīlism; and so Paul Casanova in 1898, discovering a manuscript of Risāla al-Jāmiʿa (Daftary 2007, 28 and 235; Hamdani, Soufan 2019, 10–11). Corbin (1964, 190) openly and radically affirmed that the Ikhwān belonged to Ismāʿīlism. He gave an esoterical interpretation of the religious, philosophical, and the Brotherhood rites described in Epistle 50 (Corbin 1950). Hamdani (1996, 146) considers this treatise to be “the most explicitly Shīʿi or Ismāʿīlī” of the entire encyclopedia. The main lines of Corbin’s presentation are shared, though in more nuanced terms, by Mattila 2016. Corbin was followed by Marquet (1968, 1071) who stressed their attacks on Muʿtazilite and Ashʿarite ideas. Stern (1964, 416–417) and Diwald (1975, 26ff.) remarked that the Epistles exercised their influence on the Ismāʿīlis only from the twelfth century. More recently, De Smet (2014–2015, 296) noted that it was not until the 12th century that the Tayyibi Ismāʿīlis incorporated the Brethren of Purity to support their philosophical systems. However, the epistles in themselves can hardly be traced back to the Ismāʿīlī sphere. The concepts and historical ideas that are at least close to those of the Shīʿa – such as deprecation of the slaughter of Karbalā’, the allegorical interpretation of the Qur’ān and prophecy, or the aversion to political governments and the hope that they will fall when the present septenary cycle comes to an end – show according to Stern (1964, 421) and later Bausani that the authors were representative of an Ismāʿīlī tendency, but not of the official daʿwa (propaganda) (Bausani 1977, 323; Bausani 1978, 14–16 and 267, note 1). Almost half a century later, in a fundamental article, Krinis (2013, 311 and note 2) observed that the Brethren belonged to a “unique and highly influential Shīʿī Ismāʿīlī circle” in the first three quarters of the 10th century. This, in opposition to Netton 1991 who regarded the Brethren as representatives of Arabic Neoplatonism. Considering Epistles 50 and 48, Bausani agrees, albeit cautiously, on the hypothesis of an Ismāʿīlism of the Ikhwān (Bausani 1978, 270; 278 and note 2), identified in their “encyclopedic” approach to knowledge (Bausani 1985, 145; cf. also Daftary 1998, 2 and 83). Marquet 1973, on the other hand, recognizes in the encyclopedia (in Epistle 48 in particular) the official Ismāʿīlī organization at the time (see also Marquet 1981, 95; Marquet 1998, 5, 7–8), and remarks that the propaganda appeals here to philosophers, mystics, and rulers. According to Hamdani (1996, 150), the event expected by the Ikhwān is the advent of the Fatimids. Epistle 48, Marquet claims, was written before 910, and almost entirely preserved in its original form; but even if it was composed after the advent of the Fatimids, its meaning would not have been perverted (Marquet 1984, 77–78). Other scholars have remarked that even when discussing number seven, so linked to Ismāʿīliyya, the Ikhwān criticize the “supporters of the seven” (Hamdani 1979, 68; Netton 1996, 28–29). Non-Ismāʿīlī ideas can also be found in the work, for example the invitation to celibacy proper of Sufism (but for contrary views see above). In general, the evidence supporting such theories derives mostly from doctrines or parts of doctrines hinted at in the encyclopedia. In denying the Brethren’s Ismāʿīlī commitment, for instance, Netton (1996, 28) remarks that, if the issue of such an allegiance is widely debated, scholars have much less addressed the “broader topic [...] of whether the Ikhwān al-Safā’ should even be considered to be Muslims.” The enormous variety of its contents and, often, their inconsistency seem to have hindered scholars from reaching unanimous conclusions on the authors’ religious (or rather ideological) commitment and, consequently, on their goals. The main lines of research in this field were resumed in Kraemer 1992, 165–178; cf. Hamdani 1999, 79; Hamdani, Soufan 2019, 10 ff.).
In De Smet 2022, the possible influence of Abū Hātim al-Rāzī’s Aʿlām al-nubuwwa (‘The Signs of Prophecy’) on al-Fārābī’s concept of the ruler of the perfect city is examined. This does not imply that al-Fārābī was an Ismāʿīlī, as the Ismāʿīlī tradition considers the work zāhir (“exoteric”); it therefore circulated freely outside the restricted circle of the Ismāʿīlī community – and in fact was widely disseminated throughout the Islamic world. There are also notable similarities with the “political” epistles of the Ikhwān al-Safā’, although al-Fārābī’s terminology is Aristotelian, while that of the Ikhwān is Neoplatonic. It could therefore be hypothesized that the Ikhwān were not familiar with al-Fārābī’s political writings, which were composed towards the end of his life. Like the Kitāb Aʿlām al-nubuwwa, the Rasā’il were not part of the esoteric literature of the Ismāʿīlī daʿwa at that time and were more widely disseminated than in the restricted circle of initiates. Despite the recent links established between the encyclopedia and Maslama al-Qurtubī, De Smet eventually notes that “La position dominante encore aujourd’hui accorde foi au témoignage d’Abū Ḥayyān al-Tawḥīdī selon lequel les Rasā’il auraient été composées par un groupe de clercs a Baṣra entre 360/970 et 370/980, donc apres la mort d’al-Fārābī, ce qui signifie que les Ikhwān seraient tributaires du philosophe” (De Smet 2022, 83–84).
4. The extant corpus
The encyclopedia consists of 52 treatises divided into four sections on the introductory (al-riyādiyya), natural, psycho-rational and metaphysical-theological sciences.
Two additional Epistles, entitled “Comprehensive Epistle” (al-Risāla al-Jāmiʿa) and “Supercomprehensive Epistle” (Risāla Jāmiʿat al-Jāmiʿa) are thought to complete the corpus and explain its esoteric (hidden) meanings. Two versions of the Jāmiʿa are extant. One is currently ascribed to al-Majrītī, the Spanish scientist and astronomer who is alleged to have transmitted the Epistles to Spain. Godefroid de Callataÿ (2014, 200) identifies this personage with Maslama al-Qurtubī (see above). The other is ascribed to Ahmad ibn ʿAbd Allāh ibn Muhammad ibn Ismāʿīl ibn Jaʿfar al-Sādiq, the second of the three “veiled” (mastūr) imāms who were intermediate between Muhammad ibn Ismāʿīl and ʿAbd Allāh, the founder of the Fatimid dynasty. Recent studies on aspects of this work by Baffioni (2011b, 2012). According to De Smet, however, the existence of the imām Ahmad is not grounded on any reliable historical evidence (De Smet 2017, 154–155). The attribution of the Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’ and of Risāla al-Jāmiʿa to one of the “hidden imām” would be a late forgery dating not beyond the 13th century (De Smet 2017, 157 and 160). The Risāla Jāmiʿat al-Jāmiʿa is also (Tamir s.d., 18) ascribed to Ahmad, which strengthens the link of the corpus with the Ismāʿīlī tradition. While one cannot deny formal and substantial relationship between the encyclopedia and the “Comprehensive” Epistle, the “Supercomprehensive” Epistle is never cited in the Rasā’il, and it has been recognized by Kacimi 2015, 331 as an outcome of the Ismāʿīlization of the Ikhwanian corpus. Hamdani 2008 hypothesizes a more recent compilation for the Risāla al-Jāmiʿa. The Institute of Ismaili Studies, London, is currently printing a new critical edition of the Risāla al-Jāmiʿa by Mourad Kacimi, the first to be conducted on a considerable number of manuscripts, explicitly indicated and described in detail. The edition is accompanied by a commentary and an annotated English translation by Carmela Baffioni.
Each Epistle of the encyclopedia starts by stating its particular goal. All of them contain a core of technical teachings and a conclusion regarding the haqīqa, the inner meaning of the contents. The texts contain frequent invocations to the learning “brethren” – that is, the elect who are studying the sciences – that enhance their didactical and exhortative style; these invocations mean that the students will be awakened “from the sleep of matter and the negligence of ignorance” if they apply themselves assiduously to study “with the assistance (ta’yyid) of a spirit coming by God.”
The Epistles vary in length and their style is plain. There are, however, numerous ambiguities, due to language and vocabulary, often of Persian origin, and to mistakes in the transmission of the text. Bausani (1978, 11) thinks the authors were of Persian origin (cf. now Hamdani, Soufan 2019, 5). In general, however, the doctrines are fully and clearly exposed, with repetitions where necessary to the didactic function of the treatises.
Diwald (1975, 12–15) has even wondered whether there were in fact several authors of the encyclopedia because of the use at times of the first person singular. The basic question, of course, is whether the authors unify the doctrines of more numerous groups, as suggested by the different contexts and even their inconsistencies.
The Ikhwanian encyclopedia is typical of the changes in Greek science and philosophy during the tenth century as a result of the increasing Shīʿa influence. In the ninth century and at the beginnings of the tenth century, the prominent philosopher Abū Yūsuf Yaʿqūb b. Ishāq al-Kindī (d. ca. 870) had already developed single philosophical doctrines (e.g. in cosmology or psychology; an examination of the contents of Epistle 41 On definition and descriptions in the light of al-Kindī’s treatise with the same title is made by Poonawala in Baffioni, Poonawala 2017, 277 ff.). Though elaborating them in an original way, al-Kindī had not tried to combine such doctrines with the basics of Muslim faith. Theological considerations remain parallel with philosophical issues. The physician Muhammad ibn Zakariyyā’ al-Rāzī (d. ca. 925), mainly interested to natural philosophy, had even questioned the legitimacy of prophecy.
At the time of al-Fārābī (d. 950), ancient knowledge will be considered as an organic whole – not only a sum of theoretical elaborations, but as a real encyclopedia of sciences. It should provide at every level, from the most elementary to the most complex, the necessary premises for the acquisition of ultimate knowledge – the knowledge of God. Then, authentically Muslim thought – religious in the strict sense – begins with the substitution of the schemes of Greek philosophy for those of the Sacred Text. This is what I. Netton (1989) defined as “the progressive estrangement from the Qur’anic Creator Paradigm.” Ancient knowledge is the basis on which the patrimony of faith is built: sciences are significant not merely in themselves so much as a partial reflection of the single and unique divine Being. See Heck (2008, 2002) for interesting articles that focus on both the Ikhwān’s and al-Fārābī’s “willingness to turn to philosophy to explain religion and trace its boundaries.”
The sense of truly “Muslim” science is largely a product of the ideological commitment of the authors. Consequently, scholars arrived to consider the Ikhwān al-Safā’ as representatives of a “humanistic approach” to Islam (e.g., Albert Reyna 2007). This view, however, is challenged by their attitude, to see the ultimate goal of their gnosiological experience as an attempt of separating the soul from the ties of matter and purifying it to achieve happiness in the hereafter (see also Reymond 2012, 126; Raymond 2014, 150). For them, purification can be reached by following prophetic revelation with the help of reason. Certainly, the study of ancient sciences is not viewed, as by “orthodox theologians”, as a vehicle of heresy and even atheism. Rather, sciences explain the underlying reality of the universe and so allow rational understanding of the contents of Revelation and of religious Law. As Reymond (2012, 143) puts it, the Brethren’s intellectual attitude demonstrates “une mentalité en construction,” announcing “une avancée dans une mentalité forgée par le terminus ad quem prévisible d’une autorité du dogme achronique et indépassable.”
The blending of scientific and religious issues is evident from the beginning in the encyclopedia. Sciences should be the main topic in the first and the second sections and, partially, in the third, and theology in the rest of the corpus. In spite of the fact that ancient texts are always quoted with great accuracy from a philological point of view, the Ikhwān deeply rework the Greek sources in line with their goals that are completely different from those of the ancients. Thus religion should not be underestimated in order to attain the best comprehension of its various contents and real aims.
5. The classical heritage
Let us approach the first feature of the encyclopedia, that is, its reworking the of foreign “scientific” contents. Various cultural elements come together in the Epistles: Babylonian, Indian and Iranian astrology, Indian and Persian narrative, biblical quotations and cabbalistic influences, references to the New Testament and Christian gnosis. A good survey of these contents can be found in Netton 1991, 53 ff., 89 ff. More recently, the scholar has emphasized as “Philosophically, the Rasā’il [...] constitute a marvelous epitome of the mixing of Aristotelianism and Neoplatonism in the caldron of Islamic intellectual endeavour” (Netton 2009, 109). In spite of the commixtion of Aristotelian and Neoplatonic ideas – e.g., for identifying Aristotle’s active cause with the faculties of the Universal Soul, “Aristotle’s terminology is all-pervasive in the Rasā’il” (ibid., 111–112). Most attention is paid to the Greeks, from the so-called “pre-socratics” to Plato, Aristotle, Plotinus and the Stoics. The encyclopedia can thus be considered a compendium of foreign sciences, deserving attention even by those who are only interested to ascertain the extent of what the Arabs knew of ancient doctrines at that time.
Comparisons between the Ikhwān’s quotations and the extant Arabic versions of classical works often show that they might have used the same translations at our disposal now. When such comparisons are not possible, the ancient excerpta usually correspond to the extant original texts. We should conclude, then, that in quoting, reporting – and, perhaps, translating – ancient sources the Ikhwān display the same philological and philosophical expertise associated with the scholars to whom we owe the flourishing of the translation movement in Baghdād. In some cases, they have even preserved the only Arabic fragments of Greek authors known to us, as exemplified by the well-known case of the story of Giges from Plato’s Republic in Epistle 52. (The story of Giges is analyzed in Baffioni 2001, 168–170, 175–178). Platonic references in the encyclopedia are also scarce. The majority of them are found in the fourth section and concern the trial and death of Socrates. The Ikhwān are also informed about the Platonic view on pleasures and about Plato’s conception of the soul as consisting of three distinct parts: the rational soul, which resides in the head; the irascible soul, which resides in the heart and is the seat of courage; and the appetitive soul, the seat of desire, which resides in the abdomen (III, 68, 4–6). The Platonic references are religiously rather than philosophically oriented. That can perhaps be explained by the influence of the Hellenistic curricula scientiarum (courses of study) designed for philosophers. These began by a reflection on the Stoic bios theoretikòs (the philosophical attitude towards life), continued with Aristotelian works representing the “scientific” side of knowledge, and ended with Platonic writings, representing the “theological” knowledge (D’Ancona Costa 1996, 30–31). The religious approach to ancient heritage leads the Ikhwān to consider philosophy as an “imitation of God according to human capacity.” This definition immediately clarifies Hellenism as the authors’ first theoretical and historical reference. Their source is here Plato or, rather, his Hellenistic reading (Kraus 1986, 99, note 4).
Although the Ikhwān appear widely Aristotelian (for instance, for their presentation of the terrestrial world or the theory of knowledge rooted in sensation), the wealth of the available sources led the “Pure Brethren” to support their doctrines by a variety of theoretical models, often melted together (which even affects the consistence of the Ikhwanian idea of God, Islamic and Neoplatonic at the same time, Netton 2009, 108).
The first topic addressed in the first section are the so-called “quadrivium” (a Latin term meaning “the four ways”) sciences (arithmetic, geometry, astronomy and music): Epistle 1 deals with arithmetic, Epistle 2 with geometry, Epistle 3 with astronomy and Epistle 5 with music. Arithmetic, geometry and music are later approached together in Epistle 6 On proportions. Between these two treatises another one is added, Epistle 4 On geography: ʿilm al-hay’a (literally “cosmography”) was evidently considered part of astronomy – but Epistles 4 and 5 are copied in an inverted order in some MSS.
References for the various sciences are, generally identifiable: Euclid, Nicomachus and sometimes even Archimedes for mathematical tenets (Epistles 1, 2 and 6); Ptolemy supports astronomy and geography (Epistles 3 and 4); the Pythagoreans and again Nicomachus are the sources for musical theory (Epistles 5 and 6). The Greeks already saw arithmetic and geometry as the necessary, though not unique, means of attaining philosophical knowledge.
Much of this section is devoted to logic, the “instrument” of sciences according to Aristotle and a view widely shared by Muslims (see Epistles 10–14). These treatises take the place of grammar, logic and rhetoric, that in Middle Ages constituted the “trivium” (in Latin: “the three ways”) sciences and were the basis of a “liberal arts” education. There is no place for poetry or for rhetorical devices in the encyclopedia. Dialectics increases damaging opposition among the learned. Although the Ikhwān appear interested in spoken language and even in phonetics, they never approach grammar as a science. Rather, they examine the technique of the “universal” form of language – logic. In the well-known 10th century debate on the superiority of grammar or of logic, they might have sided with the Christian logician Abū Bishr Mattā ibn Yūnus more than with the grammarian Abū Saʿīd al-Sirafī (cf. Heck 2008, 11 for a new perspective on this issue). “Trivium” was considered preparatory for the “quadrivium,” which was in turn considered preparatory for the study of philosophy and theology. The “trivium” and “quadrivium” sciences are described in the encyclopedia in an original way as distinct from that of other Muslim writers as well as the Latin west (de Callataÿ 2005, 61–62). Hellenistic influence is remarkable even when the Ikhwān rely on Aristotelian logic. The logical treatises include paraphrases of Porphyry’s Isagoges, which the later Greeks considered to be the first book of Organon (Rhetoric and Poetics were taken to be its last books). It is followed by Aristotle’s Categories, De interpretatione, Prior and Posterior Analytics.
This choice of texts shows that the Ikhwān conform to the “old” tradition that restricted research to the first Books of the Organon, not to that of their great contemporary al-Fārābī, who expanded it to the whole logical corpus. This might be due to the religious aims of the encyclopedia. Religious matters can only be treated by relying on the sound (sahīh) method for knowledge, while procedures aiming at mere persuasion or linked to the attainment of that which is useful (and not true) are not to be employed. Logic is no longer a simple instrument of science as it was for Aristotle, but a true science, perhaps the most important one. The Brethren call it “the scale of sciences” through which the wise men are able to discern “true from false in speeches, right from wrong in opinions, truth from vanity in beliefs and good from evil in acts” (cf., e.g., Epistle 7, I, 268, 14–16).
Epistle 7 On the theoretical arts carefully sketches the Ikhwān’s epistemological vision. A sort of “table” of human sciences is given (I, 266, 14–274, 21). There are three kinds of sciences in hierarchical progression: the “propaedeutical” (or preparatory, al-riyādiyya again; “a designation not absolutely unambiguous” according to de Callataÿ in El-Bizri; de Callataÿ 2017, 78 ff.), those imposed by religious Law (al-sharʿiyya al-wadʿiyya) and the “philosophical sciences allowing the full comprehension of truth” (al-falsafiyya al-haqīqiyya, higher than the religious sciences). The sciences listed first in the table are labelled “propaedeutical” just as the “trivium” and “quadrivium” sciences of the encyclopedia, but here the term is used in a totally different sense. It concerns matters of practical utility, such as reading and writing, grammar and poetry (someway close to the “trivium” sciences), but also magic, mechanics, arts, trades, history and so on. Although the Ikhwān state that the sciences of the third group – the “philosophical” in the higher sense of the word – are the object of their Epistles, they do not coincide exactly with the contents of the encyclopedia, at least, with those of the corpus now available. So, the table can be considered as evidence of the fact that the whole encyclopedia has been produced during a very long period of time. On the one hand, it might have been retained as a first draft of the future enterprise; on the other, it shows the further elaborations of the corpus over the centuries.
Epistles 7 and 8 explicitly recall the Aristotelian division of the theoretical and practical sciences. Epistle 7 is extensively based on Aristotle (when the Ikhwān introduce the nine “philosophical questions,” they are thinking of the Aristotelian categories, cf. I, 262, 14–266, 7; Epistle 29, III, 35, 6–7; Epistle 40, III, 345, 6–346, 6; Epistle 42, III, 513, 14–16 and 514, 13–516, 5). However, the ultimate goal of the scientific investigation is identified with the path towards hereafter and even connected to asceticism where scientists and prophets follow the same way: Aristotelian science is linked to the Ismaʿili teaching (taʿlīm, cf. I, 274, 20–275, 4). The “programmatic” aim of Epistle 7 leads us to consider it as the ideal introduction to the whole corpus.
A different type of source can be found in de Callataÿ 2020, which discusses the tenfold classification of the sciences contained in Ghāyat al-hakīm. Five of these disciplines are said to be compulsory “for the legislators,” while the other five are said to be compulsory “for the philosopher.” Hellmut Ritter and Martin Plessner defined this theory as “ein Unikum in der umfangreichen Einteilungsliteratur”. Now de Callataÿ compares a rich collection of texts containing a similar classification. He concludes that Middle Persian literature is a more plausible formative influence on the conception of tenfold classifications of knowledge than Greek literature. In this regard, I would like to draw attention to the article by Agostini and Thrope 2020. Here, the epistles are compared with the Bundahishn, one of the most important Zoroastrian texts redacted in the 9th century. The interpretation of the encyclopedia naturally aligns with the nature and cultural origins of the Bundahishn.
On the other hand, the authors’ Ismāʿīlī commitment is proven by the fact that in the complementary treatise On the practical arts the ancient “banausic” (utilitarian) activities are dealt with which were held in high esteem in Ismāʿīlism (cf. Lewis 1943; Marquet 1961; and, more recently, Yasien 2006 and Daftary 2007, 115).
Although the content of the first section is the most “uniform,” inconsistencies are found already in it. This is especially clear in Epistle 9, which portrays the “ideal wise man” from the standpoint of the encyclopedia, where moral edification is never separated from theoretical teaching. The approach is more than an echo of the well known Aristotelian division of philosophy: it stems from the view of the Ikhwān that he who searches for true wisdom must be endowed with a true mind as well as a pure heart. Epistle 9 breaks the series of the scientific treatises. Various moral behaviours are considered, with the support of a long series of anecdotes about prophets and wise men, which provide textual evidence that the Ikhwān may in practice have found asceticism (Sufism?) as another way of attaining or “enhancing” purification (cf. Epistles 6, 16 and 24). The recent critical edition with English translation and commentary by Alí-de-Unzaga (2024) illustrates in detail the epistle in its relationship with the corpus and with respect to the Qur’ān and Prophetic Tradition, Greek sources, Arabic adab literature, scientific literature, and Ismāʿīlī literature.
The composed and eclectic character of the whole is even more evident in the three other sections. In the second section, the Epistles 15–22 follow the Hellenistic arrangement of Aristotle’s works on physics. Epistle 15 echoes the themes addressed in the Physics. In Epistle 16, entitled, On the heaven and the world, the Ikhwān are shown to be in line with the Muslim tradition which transformed the ancient De caelo into a new book De caelo et mundo. Epistle 17 deals with De generatione and corruptione. Epistle 18 about meteorological phenomena and Epistle 19 about minerals recall the contents of Meteorology I–III and IV respectively. Meteor. IV, sometimes considered spurious and “the first chemical work in ancient world” according to scholars, was the basis of the theories of “chemical” or “alchemical” transformations in Islamic sciences and of mineralogy. The Ikhwanian treatise deals with mineralogy, geology and gemmology and in the correspondence established between the celestial and sub-lunar worlds, between the stars and minerals, it expresses one of the main tenets of alchemy. Further Aristotelian echoes are found in Epistle 24 On sense and sensation, to which Epistle 35 On intellect and intelligible corresponds in the third section. After topics concerning nature, such as the human body in Epistle 23, conception in Epistle 25, and man as microcosm in Epistle 26 [on the relationship between micro- an macrocosm see Maukola, 2009 and, in quite a new perspective, Nokso-Koivisto, 2011) the most important topic for the Ikhwān, the human spiritual dimension is addressed. It is discussed in terms of the relationship between soul and body in Epistles 27 e 28, life and death in Epistle 29, and pleasures in Epistle 30. The Aristotelian theory of the immovable mover, which is introduced in Epistle 37 On love, to explain the movement imparted to stars by the heavenly Universal Soul accomplishes its religious meaning. It serves to confirm the love human beings feel for permanence and their hatred for death: God is the most beloved as the everlasting cause of all beings.
On the other hand, natural treatises reflect the availability of the rich range of mineralogical, botanical and agricultural works, but none of the works by Aristotle on minerals or plants were known to the Arabs. The corpus aristotelicum on animals reached them (apart from the De partibus and the De generatione animalium) in an abridged form under the title of Kitāb al-hayawān, but Epistle 22 On animals is quite far in its content and goals from the Aristotelian corpus. In fact, it places the whole matter within the well-known metaphysical dispute on the superiority of man on animals (besides some attempts of viewing it even in an “ecological perspective”; see Darraz 2012; Raymond 2014, 151).
In more recent years, the Epistle on Animals has attracted the attention of numerous scholars. In particular, the so-called “prologue” to the epistle has been the subject of study. This text contains an esoteric interpretation and is, at least in part, consistent with the Ismāʿīlī tendencies of the Ikhwān. This is the view of de Callataÿ (2018). However, various themes such as a) God’s Intimates, b) Seventy/Seventy-Two, c) Seven, d) Yaʿsūb (the Commander of the Bees, and a nickname of ʿAlī ibn Abī Tālib), e) the Return of the Conjunction, and f) the function of the equator in the text reveal numerous elements of various origins. These confirm the Ikhwān’s syncretism more than anything else. De Callataÿ (2022) also focuses on the prologue to the Epistle on Animals. Although this text is similar in length to some of the epistles in the encyclopedia and is undoubtedly deeply influenced by Aristotelian thought on animals, it cannot be fully understood without recognising the influence of the Pythagoreans and Neoplatonic thought. The prologue also highlights the importance of the “perfect man”, the syncretic man that the Brethren introduce at the end of the Epistle and is the incarnation of the noble angel in potentiality that they mention at the beginning of the treatise. This establishes the unity and coherence of the entire treatise, providing a foundation for the ancient principle that the humans’ condition is hellish as long as the soul is incapable to move to the angelic rank. Pythagorean influences are evident in the idea that certain animals are perfectly constituted because their natures combine the nine arithmetical units. Considering the remarkable numbers found in the human body, such as the twelve orifices, twenty-eight vertebrae, and three hundred and sixty veins, the Ikhwān conclude that existing beings follow the nature of numbers. Animals and humans are also correlated with astral cycles of varying lengths. Particular attention is paid to the passage stating that, at the end of each 7,000-year cycle the souls of the beasts (bahāʾim) are enabled to get freed from their condition, because they are, of all animals, those that are the most badly treated. The transformation of their animal souls into human souls would be a compensation for their former miserable condition. This statement opens up the possibility that the Ikhwān believed in metempsychosis.
Emphasis had already been given to the transmigration and survival of the soul by Stern 1964, 421. In recent years, Lory 2018 has already touched upon the topic, when he examines the conception of the human being in adab and falsafa with Jāhiz (d. 867), Ibn Miskawayh (d. 1030) and the Ikhwān al-Safā’. Once again, the central idea is that humanity is only fulfilled in its higher state, that of the sage or prophet. Holiness is the only differential attribute of humans with respect to animals. Metempsychosis is also addressed in Almutawa 2018. The author claims that the Ikhwān al-Safā’ were intentionally inconsistent in their views on bodily resurrection and the afterlife: they accepted the resurrection of the body, but rejected it within the same section of their treatise on resurrection for pedagogical reasons. Assuming that the physical is inferior to the spiritual, and that the material world causes suffering whereas the spiritual world contains bliss, heaven cannot be a physical place; but hell is certainly the soul’s embodiment. This thesis demonstrates that the Ikhwān developed an original method of Qur’anic interpretation for their time (although it was typical of the 12th/14th centuries). It combined the Neoplatonic (scientific) view with the Qur’anic view. The Ikhwān accept the idea of metempsychosis (tanāsukh), found in Plato’s philosophy and the Arabic adaptation of Plotinus’s Enneads. In conclusion, the Ikhwān believe in the eternity of the soul, but not of the body. Mattila 2019 agrees with the idea that the Ikhwān believed in metempsychosis. The importance of this line of research is remarkable given that, despite the fact that Pythagoreanism is one of their doctrinal foundations, the Ikhwān al-Safā’ can only openly deny the doctrine of the transmigration of souls (as is the case, for example, in Epistle 42, III, 424, 15). Chowdhury 2021 returned to the importance of animal allegory itself.
De Vaulx d’Arcy’s most recent publications have also focused on the Epistle on Animals. His researches culminated in a monograph containing a new French translation of the treatise alongside a broad historical and theoretical framework. The aim is of restoring the treatise to its original context, disregarding interpretations that, since Dieterici, have linked it to modern theories (Darwinism, ecology, etc.) (de Vaulx d’Arcy, 2021). In de Vaulx d’Arcy 2020, the rhinoceros being classified as a bird shows that the Epistle on Animals marks a paradigm shift that would be finalised by the physician Ibn Abī al-Ashʿath in the mid-10th century. This shift involves replacing an “eco-biological” criterion with an anthropological one. This is in accordance with the idea that humans are the organising principle of the animal world. One topic arising from the Epistle on Animals is the domestication of animals by humans (al-taskhīr), which is examined in de Vaulx d’Arcy 2021–22 in relation to its influence on later thinkers. This doctrine emerged in the 3rd/9th century, a period pivotal in the development of Islamic sciences, and the era in which de Vaulx d’Arcy dates the epistles, ascribing them to al-Sarakhsī.
The influence of the Epistle on Animals on the contemporary world is evident in the latest work by the anthropologist and thinker José Antonio Jáuregui (1941–2005), the children’s story Juicio a los humanos (edited by his son Eduardo Jáuregui, RBA Bolsillo 2009). In an imaginary forest, animals gather to judge humans, accused of heinous crimes. An owl acts as judge, a cobra as prosecutor and a dog as defence lawyer, among other characters. It is a profound analysis of our society and the contemporary world (Villanueva-Romero 2020).
The authors’ view of embryology (Epistle 25) is also a collection from different sources. On the one hand, the Ikhwān were not physicians, though they display extensive knowledge of anatomy and share the Aristotelian thesis of the origin of the embryo from the sperm and menstrual blood, while they did not accept the ancient Hippocratic theory as developed by Galen, of a female sperm coexisting with that of the male in the formation of the human being. On the other hand, they emphasize an astronomical/astrological approach to embryology that was not in Greek sources. It is considered to be a new idea introduced by Islamic scientists, from whom it passed into the Latin world. Greek sources for Epistle 37 on love also vary.
The real deviation from Aristotelianism is Epistle 20 On nature. In that it shows how nature as taught by Aristotle was received and theorized by the authors, this treatise could serve as the perfect introduction to the section on natural sciences. However, its main part regards angelology. It also introduces a Neoplatonically inspired conception of Nature, suggestive of Ismāʿīlī philosophical positions, as Abū Yaʿqūb al-Sijistānī’s representation of Nature as “agent power” and “principle of movement”.
Though the Ikhwān never mention Plotinus explicitly, the third section opens with two treatises that deal with rational beings as understood by the Pythagoreans (Epistle 32) and the Ikhwān al-Safā’ (Epistle 33). These treatises demonstrate beyond doubt that these authors considered themselves true Muslim Pythagoreans. Pythagoras is said to be “a monotheist from Harrān.” The Pythagorean idea of the one as the principle of numbers, and not as a number itself explains that God is the origin of beings, and not a being like others. If God is like the one, the Active Intellect is compared to number 2, the Universal Soul to number 3 and Nature (or Matter) to number 4 (cf. e.g. Epistle 40, III, 347, 5). The encyclopedia resumes Pythagorean mathematical and musical theories and adopts a numerological approach on the basis of the Pythagorean tenet that “existing beings correspond to the nature of number.” The whole reality is considered under a numerological perspective. Every aspect of nature – and even of religion – follows a numeric pattern. De Vaulx d’Arcy 2019a gives the French translations of Epistles 1 On Arithmetic, 2 On Geometry, 6 On Arithmetic, Geometric, and Harmonic Proportions, 29 On the Wisdom of Death and Life, 33 On the Intellectual Principles according to the Brethren of Purity, and 50 On the Species of Governance. The A. states that “Justement, le génie des Épītres consiste, selon nous, à avoir su explorer comment les mathématiques nous aident à résoudre des problèmes philosophiques” (2019, 82). He also alludes to the distinction made by the Ikhwān between themselves and the Pythagoreans, whose doctrine is described in Epistle 32. He claims that the Pythagoreans are not just an ancient school, but an active one. This is indicated by two elements. Firstly, the philosophical doctrine attributed to the Pythagoreans cannot be reduced to any known Hellenistic form. Secondly, the biographical elements of Pythagoras are transposed into the unique geographical setting of the city of Harrān. Therefore, it can be presupposed that among the Sabians of Harrān there are thinkers who can be identified with Pythagoreanism. De Vaulx’s strong theoretical approach seems to draw a parallel between various ontologies based on a set of principles and number sequences. He also seems to attribute to the Ikhwān the idea that such ontologies progressively approach the truth of monotheism. “Elle est une méta-ontologie, qui « rend à chacun ce qui lui est dū », c’est-à-dire qui ne se crispe pas sur une ontologie particulière associée à un nombre de principes (le dualisme des Zoroastriens, la trinité des Chrétiens,…), mais leur donne à chacune un rang dans la suite des entiers naturels. La vérité est la suite ordonnée des vérités” (2019, 324–325). The Ikhwān follow the Pythagoreans because the Pythagorean school pays tribute to the divine organisation of the world and aims to discover musical harmony, both instrumental and cosmic.
The fact that every aspect of nature follows a numerical pattern should demonstrate that the cosmos – also introduced as a “macranthropos” (man as the pattern of the external world as a whole) in Epistle 34 – is organized according to recurrent and well-determined quantitative models, being at the same time completely dependent on God, the principle of everything just as one is the root of each number. According to de Callataÿ, Aristotelian themes are “reshaped”, for didactic purposes, in a Neoplatonic frame (El-Bizri; de Callataÿ 2017, 88), so that those who organized the corpus in its final version “are definitely to be ranged amongst hard-line Neoplatonists in medieval Islam” (El-Bizri; de Callataÿ 2017, 89). An indirect influence of the Ikhwān’s mathematical terminology is evident in Abraham Ibn Ezra’s commentary on Qohelet 7:27 (Robinson 2021, 290 ff.).
Among the other philosophical schools and doctrines quoted in the encyclopedia an important role is played by hermetism (the religion of the philosophical elite in Ancient Egypt, founded by Hermes Trismegistus), as in Epistle 3 On astronomy and, more broadly, in Epistle 52 (Marquet 1973, 1988). Ancient theories on the movements of the stars will finally evolve in Epistle 36 into that which, following Cumont, G. de Callataÿ (1996, 36–37) has defined as a “fatalisme astral.”
6. The religious component
Just like philosophy, as a way towards salvation, is an imitation of God and implies that the disciple is provided not only of an acute mind, but also of a pure heart (through which God will be recognized as the sole and the supreme teacher in knowledge and deeds, as the Holy Book demonstrates, cf., e.g., Qur., II, 31: ‘And He taught Adam the names’, mentioned in Epistle 28, III, 18, 14–16 and in Epistle 31, III, 112, 19 and 141, 13–14; cf. also Epistle 23, II, 381, 17), the Ikhwān consider prophetic message (both esoteric and exoteric, hidden and clear) as the second necessary means for human salvation and happiness. This brings us back to the second aspect of the encyclopedia, its religious commitment.
We already saw that the Ikhwān rework the classical heritage in religious terms. They also deal with doctrinal questions linked to religion. Epistle 42 On opinions and religions, the other “programmatic” treatise of the encyclopedia that opens the fourth section, is a discussion of the basic ideas of the Brotherhood such as the multifaceted epistemological problems, the origin of the world, morals and theodicy and the imamate as well as the various doctrines critically considered by the Ikhwān, such as eternalism and dualism. It also develops the apologetic side of Ikhwanian thought.
Epistle 40 On causes and effects addresses the crucial problem of the origin of the world. The Ikhwān subvert to religious purposes Aristotle’s teleological approach that “nature does not make anything in vain.” Understanding creation, one of the basic Muslim tenets, is recognized as the highest attainment of knowledge. So, the ancients are defended from the charge of eternalism (cf. III, 356, 11–18) and, for the sake of the masses, creation is even explained through the comparison of God with a confectioner. However the Ikhwān – like the Ismāʿīlis – adopt Neoplatonic views as the best explication of the origin of the world by God. The world, then, emanates from God through the hypostases of Intellect and Soul. Emanationism is the philosophical expression of creation. This doctrine also explains the encyclopaedic structure of the treatises. The various levels of reality down to the three kingdoms of the generated beings (animal, vegetable and mineral) originate continuously through intermediaries from the One. For this reason, by acquiring all the sciences from the lowest to the highest it is possible to attain the common source of everything, the ‘science of God’ in the double sense of pertaining to God and concerning God – the ancient metaphysics (metà ta physikà) no longer indicates what comes “after” physics but what is “beyond” it. Thus, rather than a mere foreign source, Neoplatonism (merged with Neopythagorism) can be considered as the Ikhwān’s proper philosophy. Philosophy as imitation of God continues as the guiding principle of the Ikhwān’s system, together with equal emphasis on divine revelation.
From Epistle 43 onwards, the Ikhwān build their own system from a religious point of view, often in the fragmentary style typical of Muslim esoteric writings. Epistle 43 considers the way towards God through purification; then the beliefs of the Ikhwān al-Safā’ and of the so-called “Divines,” the heirs of a prophetic tradition whose origin is ascribed to the ancient wise men (Epistle 44). Epistle 45 expounds the organization of the Brotherhood based on mutual help. Epistle 46 considers the faith, not only of Islam, but also of the former monotheistic religions and of the ancient wise men. Epistle 47 considers prophecy and the imamate. Epistle 48 discusses propaganda. Epistle 49 deals with a key theme in the encyclopedia – the existence of disembodied agents in the world, based on the Ikhwān’s idea that the full truth of the Qur’ān, obscured in their time by ignorance and distortions, could only be restored thanks to the study of the rational sciences developed by the Greek philosophers. In the surviving manuscript tradition, Epistle 49 appears in two versions, a short and a long one. The short one clearly preserves an older text. The long one contains a detailed elaboration of part of the short one. The short version also consists of two parts; the second is a commentary on the Epistle by an author other than that of the first, namely Maslama al-Qurtubī al-Majrīṭī, during his stay at Basra in 936–7. At the same time, Maslama should have also composed what de Callataÿ identified as the “short version” of Epistle on Magic, to which Epistle 49 was to be an introduction. In fact, both treatises aim to prove the existence of spiritual beings: magic in all its forms consists precisely in the acts of such spiritual beings. The long version would have been composed by Maslama after his return to Cordoba. In the printed editions, the final part of the short version is added to the text of the long version, but the addition is not found in any of the MSS examined in the new edition, while it might be found in the MS on which the first printed edition was based (that of Bombay, 1887–1889); but we do not know if such MS still exists (Madelung et al. 2019, 1–3). Epistle 49 is a complex exposition of Ikhwanian cosmology, remarkably different and richer than that exposed in any other epistle. This exposition is merged with the authors’ religious vision on the relationship between God and the world (Uy in Madelung et al. 2019, 8). A new vision of the Ikhwān’s magic as the “conceptual and practical pivot” of their religious-political reform based on inclusion and tolerance is in Saif 2019; a study of the so-called “longer version” of Epistle 52 in Saif 2020. Epistle 50 discusses the various kinds of ‘administration’ (physical, spiritual, personal, familiar, etc.), the core of the Epistle being the religious and philosophical approach to God. In the new edition, the treatise appears purged of all the passages that led Corbin to his esoteric interpretation (Baffioni in Madelung et al. 2019, 148). Some MSS provide additions and/or versions radically different from those reported in the other consulted manuscripts and in the printed versions available (Baffioni in Madelung et al. 2019, Appendices A–D, 237–364; with regard to additions to other epistles see Baffioni 2019a, 2019b). Noteworthy is the addition in MS Esad Efendi 3638 that explains the story of Adam meant as the progenitor of humankind, the first speaking prophet and the heavenly imām (ed. and tr. by Baffioni in Madelung et al. 2019, 237–277; cf. also Baffioni 2020b). Apparently, Epistle 51 duly gathers up the threads of the whole (often repeating contexts of previous treatises), but its recent editor has also ascertained the existence of two versions of it, maybe even three (Alshaar in Madelung et al. 2019, 381ff.). Epistle 52 On magic is the last in the corpus, missing in some editions and considered by some scholars (Bausani 1978, 12 and 279) as spurious, and of little value, so the Risāla al-Jāmiʿa would be the true fifty-second one (cf. de Callataÿ 2011, 3). However, de Callataÿ inclines to the view that the ‘short version’ of this treatise, namely, the part approximately corresponding to the first thirty pages of the Beirut edition, is genuine (de Callataÿ 2011, 5ff).
That a text exists in different versions is not an isolated case. Two versions of Epistles 32 have been found by Walker (Walker et al. 2015, 5, 7–8). Similarly, there are two versions of Epistle 48; one is based on a group of MSS that appear to have been copied from an Ismāʿīlī specimen; the other is based on a second group of MSS, including Atif Efendi 1618. Despite the permanence of Shīʿite elements, Hamdani believes that the material in the second version has been rearranged in order to provide a version acceptable to Sunni-Sufi readers. Although one must believe to the story handed down by al-Tawhīdī, there must have been an earlier shīʿi version of the Rasā’il (Alshaar in Madelung et al. 2019, 383).
The existence of different versions of a same epistle raises questions about the history of its transmission and about how such existence should be interpreted. Which version should have priority? Should the various versions be considered to be different stages or different aspects of the same authorial project? On what basis should they be assessed? The date of a MS, although of considerable importance for determining its value, cannot be taken as the sole criterion for deciding the authenticity or the greater antiquity of a textual tradition, since a late MS may have been copied from a very ancient one. Also, due to problems related to the transmission of MSS themselves, to their dating, and to the nature of the various epistles, it is difficult to decide which versions is older or more authentic (Alshaar in Madelung et al. 2019, 382–383).
The corpus addresses other main religious issues in Muslim faith: the unity and uniqueness, and the attributes of God, angels, human destiny, good and evil, resurrection. Divine will and power are also considered when trying to explain evil in the world, though, of course, Muslim faith does not allow identifying God as the cause of evil (Epistle 19). Ultimately, the Ikhwān attribute it to human responsibility, or, better, to the responsibility of creatures in general and they do so in quite a Muʿtazilite perspective. In the hierarchical disposition of universe there are “intermediate” beings to which everything that happens in the world may be related. God, a quite remote “first beloved” is beyond all this, like the kings, whose orders are behind everything built during their reigns. Epistle 39 On the kinds of movement considers the movement of the whole cosmos, from that of the stars down to those (natural and voluntary) of human beings. Its aim is to demonstrate the existence of a God who created the world and who will bring it to an end. In Epistle 27 souls (that are self-subsistent according to the ancient doctrine) unite themselves to human bodies in order to ensure human salvation; hence wise men and prophets are said to be the “physicians of the souls” (III, 13, 7 ff.). The main religious topic is, however, resurrection, thoroughly examined in Epistle 38 where it is also considered as the supreme science (III, 288, 3–5). The theme was already addressed in Epistle 29 (wisdom is recognizable in death in that it allows the vision of God, hence the highest sorrow is damnation). On the same line, Epistle 30 states that the real “Hell” is earth, “Paradise” is heaven. However, the Ikhwān deem as “providential” the ignorance of the beauties of the afterlife, which might urge people to desire death before the natural end of life. In doing so, they are far from the Pythagorean doctrine that considered the soul as a fallen divinity imprisoned within the body as in a “tomb”.
In conclusion, whereas in Ihsā’ al-ʿulūm (“The Enumeration of the Sciences”), al-Fārābī deals with Muslim sciences such as theology (kalām) and law (fiqh), the Ikhwān mainly stress religion. In the Rasā’il, the usual distinction between philosophy/sciences (the rational or ʿaqliyya knowledge) and theology (the received or naqliyya knowledge), or between reason and faith is not valid as both are combined.
On the formal side, the religious commitment appears in the frequent Qur’anic quotations in support of ancient doctrines, sometimes through interpretations that are not in line with the theological ones. Above all, the Ikhwān appropriate the Muslim ideal of attaining happiness in this world and the hereafter and indicate in the treatises how to reach it. In physical terms it is by caring for the body, which when healthy and balanced is the condition of the purification of the soul. In metaphysical terms, the purified soul is said to be capable of knowledge, so of being saved – even though, like the Ismāʿīlis, the Ikhwān deny salvation as attainable through solely philosophy.
Prophethood is an undeniable part of the theoretical experience featured by the Ikhwān. Their political vision is linked to this and implies that attainment of happiness is considered in political terms, too, where it results in examination of what has to be accomplished to be worthy of entering the entourage of the imām. In Epistle 40 the science of the esoteric interpretation of the Qur’ān (explaining its hidden meaning) is emphasized as the highest divine gift (in doing this the Ikhwān give an interpretation of Qur., III, 7 which precedes that, much more well-known, given by Averroes two centuries later, cf. III, 344, 10–345, 5).
The second pivot of the Ikhwān’s philosophy in addition to creation is their discussion of the imamate. It has its first origin in Epistle 31 On the diversity of languages (now considered from the standpoint mentioned in the title by Albert Reyna 2009). Here the Ikhwān show that religious creeds change as a result of language transformations. More particularly, differences and contrasts within the umma due to changes in the Arabic language are linked to the debate regarding the identity of the Messenger’s deputy, which is the main cause of schism in Islam “until their time,” the Ikhwān say (cf. Epistle 31, III, 153, 8–10 and 165, 8–12). While everybody agrees on the tasks of the imām, there is a disagreement as to his identity. This is because imamate is of two kinds: prophetic and regal. Usually the tasks of the ruler are neatly distinguished from those of the prophet, because governance is a mundane business and prophecy is related to the life to come (III, 497, 5–6). On occasion these qualities are combined in a single person, who is then the delegated prophet and also the ruler (III, 495, 18–19). While the Prophet Muhammad was both prophet and ruler of the Muslim umma, so ensuring its best defence, his possible successors did not always match him in nobility. Subsequently, prophecy and governance are sometimes found in two different persons, one of whom is the prophet delegated to that community and the other the person who has been given power over them. They support one another (III, 495, 19–21). The real problem seems, then, to be the dignity of the person appointed as the caliph, which alone is the condition of a legitimate prophetical succession. The Ikhwān’s specific idea on the identity of such a person is not clear. In addition, there is apparently no distinction between the prophet, the imām or the ruler with regard to the required qualities, as Epistle 47 On the essence of divine Law demonstrates. The sole “doctrinal” solution offered in the encyclopedia seems that a ruler with ascetic tendencies can legitimately take the place of the imām.
The political ideas of the Ikhwān al-Safā’ have not been extensively analyzed by scholars, except when they have been considered as a political movement. (The Ikhwān’s interest in political issues is mainly emphasized by Eastern scholars who in general incline towards the hypothesis of their being [“filo]-Ismaʿili.” Cf. Hijab, 1982; Tamir, 1983, 89–108). In fact, the “Pure Brethren” are contrasted with the “philosophers,” who were understood to have taken an outsider position with regard to the political expectations of the society in which they lived, as a consequence of their evaluation of Plato’s Republic (cf. e.g. Kraemer 1987 and Stroumsa 2003). However, the Ikhwān do not fail to approach policy from a theoretical standpoint and the philosophical doctrines developed in their Epistles can be understood to be a functional element of their political vision. In Epistle 48, a madīna fādila (perfect city) is featured – less known but no less worthy than that proposed by al-Fārābī. This time the Ikhwān do not hide themselves behind the ancient Platonic heritage: they openly adapt a Greek idea to a Muslim situation, and various aspects of the ‘Ismailism’ of the treatise have been highlighted in Baffioni, 2014a.
Were the Ikhwān Ismāʿīlis? This of course opens the way to the second side of the argument – the Ismāʿīlī commitment of the Ikhwān.
The saying “dīn and mulk are twins” in reference to the prophet and the king empowered to perform the functions of the imām in the sense preached by the Ikhwān perfectly fits the Fatimid rulers. If this hypothesis is tenable, the debated “traditions” mentioned in Epistle 31 with reference to the misunderstandings due to the diversity of languages might be understood as the Fatimid versions of the divine Law. If the Ikhwanian “Lawgiver” is identified with the historical incarnation of the Ismaʿili faith, that is, with the Fatimid caliph, and if the “perfect city” is the one ruled by these caliphs, then the Ikhwān al-Safā’ are his duʿā’. Epistle 48, with the mention of the term daʿwa in the title, might further support the hypothesis of a project of concrete militancy by the Ikhwān.
The Ikhwān appear as the learned people who have the task of promoting propaganda (daʿwa). Sometimes they even seem to appropriate the qualities of the king-imām; in Epistle 47 they introduce themselves as the best guides for the defence of Islam in terms of al-hukamā’ wa al-falāsifa wa al-fudalā’ (“wise men, philosophers and excellent people”) and of the anbiyā’, khulafā’ al-anbiyā’ wa al-a’imma al-mahdiyūn (“prophets, successors of the prophets and well-guided imams,” IV, 126, 5–17). That the Ikhwān aim to be the guides of the elect community is further confirmed by a passage in Epistle 9. The ascetics are described as those “who know the shortcomings [of the world], who crave for the hereafter and are convinced of it, firmly rooted in its science, that is the sincere Friends of God, [His] faithful servants, the cream of all [His] creatures, whom the Creator – may [He] be exalted – called ‘persons of understanding, persons of view, persons of mind’” (I, 357, 5–9; cf. Alí-de-Unzaga 2024, 160, 2–5 Arabic, 305 transl.). These qualities correspond to those of the Ikhwān engaged, as the leaders of their community, in their philosophy of salvation; but they also fit the prophets and the imāms perfectly. From this point of view the reading of the Holy Book our authors have in mind – rather than a Shīʿi or Ismāʿīlī perspective – might be the ta’wīl performed in their own encyclopedia, where God’s Word is continually quoted and commented (Baffioni 2012b; Gobillot 2013). And they refer to the spiritual city as “our spiritual city,” which coincides with Paradise.
In Epistle 47 the legacy of the Prophet is said to be inherited by “the most intelligent” (al-ʿuqalā’ al-akhyār) which emphasizes the epistemological function of the Shīʿite caliph. In this case a temporal ruler, the “ruler imām,” is no longer necessary because the rational Law is the real guide, “incarnated” in the “rightly guided” imām and in his reason and knowledge. In contrast to Baffioni 2006, 149–150, Heck (2008, 205–209) seems to side with Netton’s reading of the intellect-guide in terms of a rational intellect.
Further elements allow a better defining of the Ikhwān’s political position. The history of early Islam is approached from a Shīʿi perspective; some important events of the prophet Muhammad’s life and mission are recalled; soon attention shifts to two fatal events which led to the defeat of Shīʿism, the battle of Siffīn and the slaughter of Karbalā’. In a passage on the struggles for imāmate, the “representatives of the Muhammadic (Muhammadiyya) Law and of the Hashimi federation” (cf. Epistle 31, III, 165, 11–12; Ormsby 2021, 117, 6–8 Ar. and 196, transl.) are opposed. If the latter are the ʿAbbasids (or even the supporters of Abū Hāshim, son of Muhammad ibn al-Hanafiyya), the former should be understood as the direct descendants of the Prophet through Fātima, whence the Ikhwān’s strict ʿAlid militancy should be demonstrated.
Another passage from Epistle 31 (III, 153, 11–156, 9) might urge to suppose that the authors’ target was the caliph al-Ma’mūn, in spite of his pro-ʿAlid policy (and political support of Muʿtazilism). The Ikhwān report on a ruler, who encouraged politico-religious controversies among the ‘ulamā’ (learned) of different persuasions, claiming for himself the right to interpret the Law on the basis of the Muʿtazilite doctrine of the created Qur’ān. Juxtaposed to him is ahl bayt al-nubuwwa (the immediate family of the Prophet: Muhammad, his daughter Fātima, his cousin and son-in-law ʿAlī and their sons, al-Hasan and al-Husayn) as the guarantors of the true tradition concerning prophetic succession. The Ikhwān could then still be identified with the supporters of the strict ʿAlid conception of the imamate, according to which the science of caliphate belongs to the family of the Prophet only.
If this hypothesis is tenable, Epistle 31 contains not only the core of the Ikhwān’s political thought, but also of their Ismāʿīlī commitment. On the other hand, their presentation of the “perfect city,” in which mutual love is the basis and the goal of the community, does not help us to ascertain whether the Ikhwān have in mind spiritual rule or a true government such as that of the Fatimid caliph, of whom they might be the duʿā’. Scholars tend to consider this “perfect city” as utopian as the Farabian (cf. e.g. Marquet 1973, 153; Hamdani 1999, 81). The defeat of evil people is also often foreshadowed in the encyclopedia (cf. e.g. Epistle 31, III, 154, 19–24 and 156, 2–3). In Epistle 4 the Ikhwān present a cyclical conception of ruling dynasties, and state that “the dynasty of the evil reached its apex,” hence only decline and diminution are to be expected in the future. According to Tibawi (1955, 37, note 4), the Ikhwān forebode here the fall of the ʿAbbasids. Cf. also Tibawi, 1978, 60.) The dynasty of the good begins when the learned agree “on a unique doctrinal school and a single religion,” commit themselves to mutual help, and desire the vision of God and doing God’s will as their [sole] reward (I, 181, 14–182, 2). In Epistle 48, the Ikhwān declare that the one whose advent in the world is expected is coming, and it will be a wonderful event (IV, 190, 13), in which the welfare of both religion and the world will be gathered. Magic, astronomy and true dreams helped them establish even the year and month of the advent of the “lord of the cycle” (sāhib al-amr) – but, of course, the date is not mentioned in the encyclopedia.
Recently, Kacimi has returned to these issues. According to Kacimi 2019, 369 ff., the Ikhwān displayed Shīʿī tendencies and opposed the ʿAbbasids. In fact, they favoured the annihilation of the “kingdom of evil” (dawlat ahl al-sharr) and the establishment of the “kingdom of good” (dawlat ahl al-khayr). The epistles conceal a political project made explicit in the Jāmiʿa (unlike the encyclopedia, the Jāmiʿa defends the Seveners’ doctrine, according to Kacimi 2019, 378). The Ikhwān may have had an Ismaili identity from the beginning, but this is not patently evident in the epistles due to both the use of taqiyya and the political strategy of not declaring one’s beliefs in order to attract individuals of different doctrinal backgrounds (Kacimi 2024, 210). For this reason, the Rasā’il do not indicate the time or place of composition, despite the authors’ claims about the antiquity of their prophetic and philosophical doctrine. Kacimi also disputes the idea that the Brethren were Qarmats, despite a passage in the Jāmiʿa stating that their doctrine is ancient. Instead, echoes of Zaydi thought can be found in the encyclopedia (Kacimi 2019, passim). Zaydism was practised by the Buyids, who were also strong advocates of philosophy (Kacimi 2019, 371 and Kacimi 2024, 202–203). Despite Moh. Jalub Farhan’s description of the Ikhwān as being opposed to the Buyid regime notwithstanding the fact that the Buyids supported science (1999, 30–31), Kacimi hypothesizes that the authors played a dual role between the Buyid and Fatimid powers. In fact, they had a relationship with al-Muʿizz, which was in opposition to the ʿAbbasids. However, shortly after al-Muʿizz’s death, ʿAdud al-Dawla appeared in Baghdad in 367/977. A Shīʿī who patronised philosophical knowledge and believed in the illegitimacy of the ʿAbbasid caliphs, he appreciated philosophy. Following his death in 982 and subsequent conflicts between his sons, prominent Ikhwān al-Safāʾ members preached in favour of the Fatimid state (Kacimi 2019, 378). De Smet and Krinis, however, reject this hypothesis (De Smet 2014–2015, 297; Krinis 2016, 33; Kacimi 2024, 204).
Grounding himself on the Sīrat ibn Ḥawshab of the Fatimid dāʿī Jaʿfar b. Mansūr al-Yaman (d. second half of the 10th century), Hamdani hypothesizes the epistles to have been written under Ahmad b. ʿAbd Allāh b. Muḥammad b. Ismāʿīl’s imāmate, who was considered as the expected imām. Ahmad, however, was not their author, but their munshi’ (“issuer”). Therefore, the Ikhwān al-Safā’ would have been a think-tank at the service of the Fatimid propaganda, a secret organization with the function of gaining support from the non-initiates (Hamdani, Soufan 2019, 1–2). The Brethren who cooperated in the final version of the encyclopedia in the tenth century might have been disguised adversaries of the Buyids, who were Shīʿites, not Ismāʿīlis. Poonawala also proposes the Rasā’il to have been written by propagandists belonging to the entourage of Ahmad, half a century after al-Ma’mūn (Walker et al. 2015, 66; De Smet 2017, 157–158). More recently, Hamdani has noted in the encyclopedia also Sunni-Sufi elements; thereby, the Ikhwān would be a secret think-tank made up of tafḍīlī Sunnis (that is, they assert the superiority of ʿAlī over all the successors of the Prophet), who hoped to replace the ʿAbbasids with a ʿAlid caliphate, displaying in their work also liberalism and religious tolerance (Hamdani, Soufan 2019, 32–33).
On the whole, the political vision outlined above appears to be founded on doctrinal elements of Ismāʿīlī nature. The division between the “elect” and the “masses” destines the former only for investigation of the curriculum studiorum at the basis of the “philosophy of salvation”. A rigid hierarchy of universe links each level of existence, physical and spiritual, to that which precedes and that which follows it where the beings that belong to the various levels cannot go beyond them. (It should be noted that this may question the idea of “evolution” in the Ikhwān that some scholars have ascribed to them; cf. e.g. Vernet Ginés 1990, 190; Marquet 1992). The didactic aims of the ruler mirror the aspect of Ismāʿīlī propaganda known as taʿlīm (lit.: “teaching”).
The influence of the Epistles on later (after the 12th century) Ismāʿīlī literature has been widely recognized (Stern 1964, 416–417; Diwald 1975, 26 ff.; Daftary 2007, 236). Their content has been transmitted and developed by subsequent thinkers of various persuasions. It is noteworthy, however, that extended literal quotations (and even translations) from the Ikhwān al-Safā’ are found in the famous Ismāʿīlī thinker and missionary Nāsir-e Khosrow (1004–1074) (see Saccone 2007, 67–68; Baffioni 2013c and Poonawala in Baffioni, Poonawala 2017, 285 ff.): this may be a proof of the use of the Rasā’il in 11th century Ismāʿīlī authors. If the Ikhwān al-Safā’ were Ismāʿīlis or in someway linked to Ismāʿīlism, then Ismāʿīlism influenced a much wider part of Islamic thought and culture than previously recognized.
With regard to an Ismāʿīlī commitment to the Ikhwān al-Safā’, some aspects of their philosophy of nature (geology, mineralogy, and botany) have been recently examined (Baffioni 2008, 2009, 2010b; de Callataÿ 2008). Mineralogy and botany have been explored in order to find similarities with Ismāʿīlī philosophy, in particular with the Ismāʿīlī thinker and missionary Hamīd al-Dīn al-Kirmānī. The result is that they share many basic views, but the Ikhwān has greater detail. Moreover, some aspects of the Ikhwān’s cosmology, and in particular their use of the term and concept of ibdāʿ, are relevant in identifying the similarities (Baffioni 2011a; 2013b; 2013d).
However, the radical change of hypotheses about the dating of the epistles after the identification of the role that Maslama al-Qurtubī would have played in them, also led to rethinking the political (and possibly messianic) beliefs of the Ikhwān and the attempts to identify the polemical targets of their assertions. Madelung remarks that while the Fatimids were used to see both Umayyads and ʿAbbasids as usurpers and enemies of ʿAlī, the Ikhwān had no longer contacts with any hidden imām, as they believe that the advent of the Mahdī has been delayed to a remote future. Therefore, they adopted a quietist attitude towards the existing regimes: their purpose was only to purify Islam through the study of ancient thought, thus preparing humanity for the advent of the true Mahdī. Maslama al-Qurṭubī remained a loyal subject of the Umayyad governor of Andalus, ʿAbd al-Raḥmān III. Hence, the Ikhwān no longer regarded the Umayyads as the inveterate enemies of the Family of the Prophet. The imām, direct descendants of the Prophet, are instead described as the only ones entitled to rule humanity, and for this purpose divinely chosen; but their persecutors – although denounced as tyrants – are not identified. Kacimi 2019 returns on the anti-ʿAbbasid polemic of the Ikhwān.
In Arjomand 2022, an opposing view is proposed that straightforwardly includes the Ikhwān al-Safā’ among the supporters of revolutionary action within the context of messianic expectations. Arjomand shares Hamdani’s opinion that the oldest epistles should be dated to the period of the “concealed imamate” (satr)—that is, after the death of Hasan al-ʿAskarī in 874 and before the establishment of the Fatimid caliphate in 909—when “the proof of God on his earth is hidden and concealed.” This is the reason why the Epistles speak of “rightly guided imams” (a’immat al-mahdiyyun) in the plural. The addressed “brother” would subsequently be the composer (munshi’) of the Epistles, identified as someone like the dāʿi Ibn Hawshab (d. 914). After Hasan al-ʿAskarī’s death, the Brethren worked for the composer of the Epistles seeking to recruit members among the Imāmiyya. The Brethren believed that the expected Imam was not hidden, but present, though his opponents refuse to recognize him (cf. Ep. 48, IV, 199). Such facts are considered to be close to Ibn Hawshab’s doctrine, behaviour, and accounts. The Qarmat leader ʽAbdān is said to have been one of the Brethren and a contributor to their encyclopedia, if not its editor. The encyclopedia would then be the “ideological spearhead of the clandestine movement of the circle of intellectuals” that he recruited with Hamdān Qarmat in the heartland of the ʿAbbasid caliphate (Arjomand 2022, 236). In their attempt at mobilizing for their “apocalyptic revolution” the Brethren ranked seven social classes among which the “artisans and craftsmen”, “businessmen and traders,” and “construction engineers and workers” are set in the three first places. “Kings, rulers, and statesmen” are placed after these, and men of religion and jurists, whom the heretical Brethren had no hope of converting, are put at the bottom of the list and sharply criticized. In doing so, they are consistent with the social background who led the earliest Ismāʻili missions. In their “revolutionary program for government and a theory of revolution,” the Brethren underline the functions of prophecy and kingship in the Persian wisdom. Philosophy is considered the most important after prophecy; al-Fārābi is even considered to be “a possible contributor” of the encyclopedia. The Brethren’s goal is the constitution of a “spiritual city” guided by reason (ʻaql) through the lawgiver (al-ra’īs wa’l-imām) who will empower the tradition of the Law. The authors consider the time of setting this new rule as the “millennial moment of the turn in power among nations” (Arjomand 2022, 237). In indicating the various changes of government and religions, they use numerology and astrology in the light of the latest findings of astronomy. The Brethren of Purity reconciled the duodecimal system of the Zodiac with the heptads of Judeo-Christian sacred history. The Ismāʿīlī dāʿi Abū ʿAbdallāh al-Shīʿī addressed his followers, to whom he imparted esoteric teachings, as “brethren” and “the People of the Good,” encouraging them to perform good deeds (ʻamal khayr) as a means of getting closer to God. By contrast, there was little or no discussion of the current clandestine ʿAlid leadership of the movement. Even in 909, after overthrowing the Aghlabids, Abū ʿAbdallāh al-Shīʿī had not yet made up his mind about the “agreed upon (al-ridā) from the Household of the Prophet” (Arjomand 2022, 246). Ultimately, following Abū’l-Shalaghlagh’s demise in late 909, he embraced Abū’l-Shalaghlagh’s nephew, whom he had never encountered, as the Mahdi. At that moment, Abū ʿAbdallāh wrote to the Brethren in Ifrīqiya that God had kept His promise and made one of His proofs appear on His earth and rescued the son of the Messenger of God. However, the Fatimid Mahdi made the Berber tribe Kutāma his natural allies against the urban Epistle intellectuals, who were led by Abū ʻAbdallāh al-Shīʿī and his brother Abū’l-ʻAbbās. On Friday 5 January 910, he ordered the preachers of Raqqada and Qayrawan to pray for him, presenting himself as God’s deputy (a term with which the Sunni majority would have been familiar) but also equating himself with the “rightly guided” imams who had been the subject of the Brethren of Purity’s discourses. On 18 February 911, the Fatimid Mahdi had Abū ʿAbdallāh and Abū’l-ʿAbbās murdered during a midday dinner. Subsequently, he rejected the millennial theory of the imminent return of Muhammad b. Ismāʻīl and altered his genealogy, claiming descent from ʻAbdallāh, the older brother of Ismāʻīl b. Jaʻfar, rather than Ismāʻīl himself. Later, Qādī al-Nuʿmān refuted the idea that the imam’s divine appointment depended on the people, or that the head of state of the “People of the Good,” as described in the Epistles, was in any way dependent on them. However, the political astrology of the Brethren of Purity was incorporated into the official ideology of the Fatimid Empire following the conquest of Egypt and Syria in the late tenth century. Conversely, Hasan Sabbah accepted the notion of inspired teaching (taʿlīm) from ʿAbdān. After seizing the fortress of Alamut in 1090 and establishing an Ismāʿīlī state comprising numerous fortresses in northern and north-eastern Iran, he, like Abū ʿAbdallāh al-Shīʿī, strictly enforced sharīʿa until the qā’im appeared. However, on 8 August 1164, Hasan II b. Mohammad b. Bozorg-Omid proclaimed the Resurrection and refused to wait for the appointed time calculated by the Brethren of Purity.
De Vaulx d’Arcy also approached the encyclopedia from a radically new perspective. In de Vaulx d’Arcy 2018, he illustrates the so-called “soteriological complementarism” of the Brethren of Purity. This concept helps us to understand how God may want salvation for all people if He saves only to those who followed His path. In order to resolve the contradictions of religious theology, the path to salvation must contain all paths as parts of a common journey. The Epistles show that no one will find salvation without everyone else. The world is built on complementary relationships: no one is self-sufficient, but together we can meet any need. If people are different, their religions will be too – and other creatures worship the Creator in their own way. The existence of multiple communities does not imply pluralism: “Le caractère régional des religions n’implique pas leur régionalisation.” Rather, diversity in creation is conceived as serving the whole, thus becoming a unity. We therefore speak of “complementarity” – doctrinal, political, and soteriological. In terms of psychophysical relationship, the soul dominates the body because, unlike the body, it is destined for eternal life. However, the body is the instrument through which the soul is fulfilled. Consequently, salvation will no longer be a reward for good deeds, but rather the capacity to enable the soul to separate from the body. Good deeds therefore contribute to common salvation. The salvation of one community will coincide with that of all communities. At the cosmic level, the soul unites with matter because it is through matter that it achieves ever higher levels of organisation and formation. Salvation will consist of allowing the Universal Soul to exist in matter, and then separate from it. This requires the mobilisation of all creation. In de Vaulx d’Arcy 2023, opposition to theological occasionalism — which denied nature — was made in the early stages of philosophy (with al-Kindī and the Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’). This affirms the independence of nature from its Creator, explaining natural changes by the idea that the world is a being that prostrates itself before God of its own volition. The relationship between the Ikhwān al-Safā’ and the Andalusi philosopher Ibn al-Sīd al-Batalyawsī is explored by De Callataÿ 2024 and Baffioni 2025. These are the first attempt to demonstrate, on textual bases, that the encyclopedia was known in Andalus since the early stages of Andalusan philosophy.
Bibliography
Texts
- Kitāb al-Maqālīd al-Malakūtiyya (The Book of the Keys to the Kingdom) by Abū Yaʿqūb Isḥāq b. Ahmad al-Sijistānī (d. after 361/971), 2011/1432 H., Ismail K. Poonawala (ed.), Tunis: Dār al-Ġarb al-Islāmī.
- Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’ wa Khullān al-Wafā’, 1957, Mustafā Ghālib (ed.), Beirut: Dār al-Sādir, 4 vols. I indicate the volume, page(s) and line(s) of each quotation or reference; addings in square brackets. (Other eds.: Bombay 1887–89, 4 vols.; Khayr al-Dīn al-Ziriklī, Cairo 1928, 4 vols.; ʿārif Tāmir, Beirut – Paris 1995, 5 vols.).
- Al-Risāla al-Jāmiʿa, Tāj Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’ wa Khullān al-Wafā’, 1949–51, Jamīl Salībā (ed.), Damascus: al-Majmaʿ al-ʿIlmī al-ʿArabī; Al-Risāla al-Jāmi ʿa, Tāj Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’ wa Khullān al-Wafā’, 19842, Mustafā Ghālib (ed.), Beirut: Dār al-Andalus.
- Risālat Jāmiʿa al-Jāmiʿa li-Ikhwān al-Safā’ wa Khullān al-Wafā’, 19702, ʿārif Tāmir (ed.), Beirut: Dār Maktabat al-Hayāt.
Editions and translations
- Albert Reyna, R.F., 1995, “La ʿRisāla fī māhiyyat al-ʿisq’ de las Rasā’il Ijwān al-Safā’,” Anaquel de Estudios Arabes, 6: 185–207.
- Alí-de-Unzaga, Omar, 2024, On Ethics and Character Traits: An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistle 9 (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), New York – London: Oxford University Press in association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- Baffioni, C., 1989, L’Epistola degli Iḫwān al-Safā’ «Sulle opinioni e le religioni», Napoli: Istituto Universitario Orientale.
- –––, 1994, Frammenti e testimonianze di autori antichi nelle Rasā’il degli Iḫwān al-Safā’, Roma: Istituto Nazionale per la Storia antica.
- –––, 2006, Appunti per un’epistemologia profetica. L’Epistola degli Iḫwān al-Safā’ «Sulle cause e gli effetti», Napoli: Istituto Universitario Orientale – Guida.
- –––, 2010a, On Logic. An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistles 10–14 (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- –––, 2013a, On the Natural Sciences. An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistles 15–21– (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- Baffioni, C., Poonawala, I.K., 2017, Sciences of the Soul and Intellect, Part III. An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistles 39–41 (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- Bonmariage C., 2008/2009, “De l’amitié et des frères: l’Épītre 45 des Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā. Présentation et traduction annotée,” Bulletin d’Etudes Orientales, 58: 315–350 and 443–444.
- de Callataÿ, G., 2003, “Ikhwān al-Safā: des arts scientifiques et de leur objectif,” Le Muséon, 116: 231–258.
- de Callataÿ, G., Halflants, B., 2011, On Magic. An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistle 52a (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- Dieterici, F., 1969, Die Philosophie bei den Arabern im X. Jahrhundert n. Chr., Gesamtdarstellung und Quellenwerke, Hildesheim: Olms (repr. Leipzig: Hinrich, 1868, 1876, 1871, 1872).
- Diwald, S., 1975, Arabische Philosophie und Wissenschaft in der Enzyklopädie. Kitāb Iḫwān aṣ-Safā (III). Die Lehre von Seele und Intellekt, Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz.
- El-Bizri, Nader, 2012, On Arithmetic and Geometry. An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistles 1 & 2 (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- El-Bizri, Nader, de Callataÿ, G., 2017, On Composition and the Arts. An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistles 10–14 (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- Gautier Dalché, P., 1988, “Epistola Fratrum Sincerorum in Cosmographia: une traduction latine inédite de la quatrième Risāla des Ihwān al-Safā’,” Revue d’histoire des textes, 18: 137–167.
- Giese, A., 1990, Ihwān as-Safā’, Mensch und Tier vor dem König der Dschinnen, Hamburg: Meiner.
- Goldstein, B.R., 1964, “A Treatise on the Number Theory from a Tenth-century Arabic Source,” Centaurus, 10: 129–160.
- Goodman, L.E., 1978, The Case of Animals versus Man before the King of the Jinn: A Tenth-century Ecological Fable of the Pure Brethren of Basra, Boston: Twayne Publishers.
- Goodman, L.E., McGregor, R., 2010, The Case of Animal versus Man Before the King of the Jinn. An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistles 22 (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- Hamdani, Abbas, Soufan, Abdallah, 2019, The Call to God. An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistle 48 (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- Ikhwān al-Safā’, 1996, Les révolution set les cycles (Épītres des Frères de la Pureté, XXXVI), Traduction de l’arabe, introduction, notes et lexique par G. de Callataÿ, (Sagesses musulmanes, 3), Beyrouth – Louvain-la-Neuve: Al-Bouraq – Academia-Bruylant.
- Jamil Ragep, F., Mimura, T., 2015, On Astronomia. An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistle 3 (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- Lizzini, O., 2009, “L’angelologia nelle epistole dei Fratelli della purezza: l’esempio della natura,” in G. Agamben, E. Coccia eds., Angeli. Ebraismo Cristianesimo Islam, Milano: Neri Pozza, pp. 1965–2012.
- Michot, J., 1974–75, “L’épītre de la résurrection des Ikhwān al-Safā’,” Bulletin de Philosophie Médiévale, 16–17: 114–148.
- Madelung, W. et al., 2019, On God and the World. An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistles 49–51 (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- Ormsby, E., 2021, On Life, Death, and Languages: An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistles 29–31 (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), Oxford: Oxford University Press in association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- van Reijn, E., 1995, The Epistles of the Sincere Brethren (Rasa’il Ikhwan al-Safa’): An Annotated Translation of Epistles 43 to 47, Montreux: Minerva Press.
- Sánchez, I., Mongomery, J., 2014, On Geography. An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistle 4 (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- Shiloah, Amnon, 1964, “L’épītre sur la musique des Ikhwān al-Safā’,” Revue des Etudes islamiques, 32: 125–162.
- –––, 1966, “L’épītre sur la musique des Ikhwān al-Safā’,” Revue des Etudes islamiques, 34: 159–193.
- Tornero Poveda, É., 2006, La disputa entre los animales y el hombre/Ijwān al-Safā’, Madrid: Siruela.
- Traboulsi, S. et al., 2016, On Companionship and Belief. An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistles 43–45 (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- Vaulx d’Arcy, G. de, 2019a, Les Épītres des Frères en Pureté (Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’) Mathématique et Philosophie, Paris: Les Belles Lettres.
- –––, 2021, Les Épītres des Frères en Pureté (Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’) Le Procès Animal de la Domination Humaine, Presentation et traduction de l’épītre 22, Paris: Les Belles Lettres.
- Walker, P.E. et al., 2015, Sciences of the Soul and Intellect Part I. An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistles 32–36 (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- Wright, O., 2010, On Music. An Arabic Critical Edition and English Translation of Epistle 5 (Epistles of the Brethren of Purity), New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- Yusufji, D.H., 1943, “The Forty-third Treatise of the Ikhwān al-Safā’,” Muslim World, 33: 39–49.
Select literature
- Agostini, D., Thrope, S., 2020, “What is the Bundahišn? Genre and Zoroastrian Literature,” Iran & the Causasus, 24(4): 378–393.
- Albert Reyna, R.F., 2007, Humanismo islámico: una antropología de las Epístolas de los Hermanos de la Pureza, Ibrahīm Albert Reyna, Almodovar del Río: Junta Islamica, Centro de Documentación y Publicaciones.
- –––, 2009, “El concepto de lenguaje en las Epístolas de los Hermanos de la Pureza,” Anaquel de Estudios Arabes, 20: 5–17.
- Almutawa, Shatha, 2018, “The Death of the Body is the Birth of the Soul”, Studia Islamica, 13(1): 56–75.
- Arjomand, Saïd Amir, 2022, Messianism and Sociopolitical Revolution in Medieval Islam, Oakland, CA: University of California Press.
- Baffioni, C., 2001, “Frammenti e testimonianze platoniche nelle Rasā’il degli Ikhwān al-Safā’,” in G. Fiaccadori ed., Autori classici in lingue del Vicino e Medio Oriente, Roma: Istituto Poligrafico e Zecca dello Stato, pp. 163–178.
- –––, 2008, “L’influence des Ikhwān al-Safā’ sur la minéralogie de Hamīd al-Dīn al-Kirmānī,” in G. de Callataÿ, B. Van den Abeele eds., Une lumière venue d’ailleurs. Héritages et ouvertures dans les encyclopédies d’Orient et d’Occident au Moyen Age, Actes du colloque de Louvain-la-Neuve, 19–21 mai 2005, Louvain-la-Neuve: Brepols, pp. 31–47.
- –––, 2009, “Le monde végétal dans la Rāhat al-ʿaql de Hamīd al-Dīn al-Kirmānī et l’influence des Ikhwān al-Safā’,” in A. Paravicini Bagliani ed., Le monde végétal. Médicine, botanique, symbolique, Tavernuzze-Impruneta (Firenze): SISMEL-Edizioni del Galluzzo, pp. 63–75.
- –––, 2010b, “La science des pierres précieuses dans l’Épītre des Ikhwān al-Safā’: entre les catalogues encyclopédiques et le commentaire philosophique,” in J. Thomasset, J. Ducos, J.-P. Chambon eds., Aux origines de la géologie de l’Antiquité au Moyen āge, Actes du Colloque International 10–12 mars 2005, Paris Sorbonne (Paris IV), Paris: Honoré Champion, pp. 75–90.
- –––, 2011a, “Ibdāʿ, Divine Imperative and Prophecy in the Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’,” in O. Ali-de-Unzaga ed., Fortesses of the Intellect. Ismaili and Other Islamic Studies in Honour of Farhad Daftary, London-New York: I.B. Tauris Publishers in Association with the Institute of the Ismaili Studies, pp. 213–226.
- –––, 2011b, “Eléments platoniciens et néo-platoniciens de la représentation d’Adam dans la Jāmi’a al-Jāmi’a,” in P. Arfé et al. ed., Adorare coelestia, gubernare terrena. International conference in honour of Paolo Lucentini, Naples 6–7 november 2007, (Instrumenta Patristica et medievalia, 58), Brepols: Turnhout, pp. 99–111.
- –––, 2012, “La figure d’Adam dans la Jāmi’a al-Jāmi’a,” in A. Paravicini Bagliani ed., Adam, le premier homme, Tavernuzze – Impruneta (Firenze): SISMEL – Edizioni del Galluzzo, pp. 115–134.
- –––, 2013b, “Le Role of the Divine Imperative (amr) in the Ikhwān al-Safā’ and Related Works,” Ishraq. Edjegodnik islamskoj filosofii (Moskva), 4: 46–70.
- –––, 2013c, “Nāsir-i Khosrow, Translator of the Ikhwān al-Safā’?,” in V. Klemm et al. ed., Sources and Approaches across Disciplines in Near Eastern Studies Proceedings of the 24th Congress, Union Européenne des Arabisants et des Islamisants, (Orientalia Lovaniensia Analecta, 215), Leuven – Paris – Walpole, MA: Peeters en Departement Oosterse Studies, pp. 319–331.
- –––, 2013d, “The Terms Ibdāʿ, al-Mubda’ al-Awwal, and Mubda’āt in the Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’,” in P. Fodor et al. ed., More Modoque. Die Wurzeln der europaischen Kultur und deren Rezeption im Orient und Okzident. Festschrift fur Miklos Maroth zum siebzigsten Guburtstag, Budapest: Forschungen fur Humanwissenschaften der Ungarischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, pp. 293–311.
- –––, 2014, “Epistle 48 of the Ikhwān al-Safā’ and their Ismā’īli Commitment,” in I. Lindstedt et al. ed., Case Studies in Transmission, (The Intellectual Heritage of Ancient and Mediaeval Near East, 1), Münster: Ugarit Verlag, pp. 11–21.
- –––, 2016, “Esoteric Shīʿism in the Additions to Ancient Manuscripts of the Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā” in M.A. Amir-Moezzi et al. ed., L’Ésotérisme shiʿite, ses racines et ses prolongements, Turnhout: Brepols, pp. 281–326.
- –––, 2018, “Embryology in an Ismāʿīlī Messianic Context. The Manuscript Tradition of the Iḫwān al-Ṣafā’,” Studia graeco-arabica, 8: 167–179.
- –––, 2019a, “Ismāʿīli Onto-Cosmological Doctrines in the Manuscript Tradition of the Iḫwān al-Safā’,” Shii Studies Review, 3: 33–58.
- –––, 2019b, “Onto-Cosmology and Hierohistory in the Manuscript Tradition of the Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’,” in O. Mir-Kasimov ed., Intellectual Interactions in the Islamic World: The Ismāʿīli Thread. London: I.B. Tauris in association with The Institute of Ismaili Studies, pp. 193–218.
- –––, 2020a, “Ikhwān al-Safā’, Encyclopedia of”, in H. Lagerlund ed., Encyclopedia of Medieval Philosophy, Dordrecht: Springer, online https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-024-1665-7_238.
- –––, 2020b, “The ‘Language of God’ in Muslim and Jewish Traditions: A Case Study,” in C. Ferrini ed., Human Diversity in Context, Trieste: EUT Edizioni Università di Trieste, pp. 121–142.
- –––, 2025, “The Andalusī Reception of Ontological Options and Cosmological Descriptions in the Ikhwān al-Ṣafā’ and al-Risāla al-Jāmiʿa: A Case Study,” in G. de Callatay, S. Moureau eds., Power, Religion, and Wisdom. Orthodoxy and Heterodoxy in al-Andalus and Beyond, Micrologus, 33: 275–299.
- Bausani, A., 1977, Review of S. Diwald, Arabische Philosophie und Wissenschaft in der Enzyklopädie Kitāb Iḫwān aṣ-Safā’ (III): Die Lehre von Seele und Intellekt. Rivista degli Studi Orientali, 51: 322–326.
- –––, 1978, L’enciclopedia dei Fratelli della Purità. Riassunto, con Introduzione e breve commento, dei 52 Trattati o Epistole degli Ikhwān as-safa’, Napoli: Istituto Universitario Orientale.
- –––, 1985, “L’enciclopedia e il mondo arabo-islamico medievale,” Rivista di Storia della Filosofia, 1: 137–146.
- de Callataÿ, G., 2005, Ikhwān al-Safa’. A Brotherhood of Idealists on the Fringe of Orthodox Islam, Oxford: Oneworld.
- –––, 2008, World Cycles and Geological Changes According to the Brethern of Purity, in P. Adamson ed., In the Age of al-Fārābī: Arabic Philosophy in the Fourth/Tenth Century, London – Turin: The Warburg Institute – Nino Aragno Editore, pp. 179–193.
- –––, 2013, “Magia en al-Andalus: Rasā’il Ijwān al-Ṣafā’, Rutbat al-ḥakīm y Gāyat al-ḥakīm (Picatrix)”, Al-Qanṭara, 34(2): 297–344.
- –––, 2014, “Philosophy and Bāṭinism in al-Andalus: Ibn Masarra’s Risālat al-Iʿtibār and the Rasā’il Ikhwān al-ṣafā’,” Jerusalem Studies in Arabic and Islam, 41: 261–312.
- –––, 2018, “‘For Those with Eyes to See’: on the Hidden Meaning of the Animal Fable in the Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Ṣafā’,” Journal of Islamic Studies, 29: 1–36.
- –––, 2020, “Dividing Science by Ten,” Studia Islamica, 115(1): pp. 1–32.
- –––, 2021, “Rutba vs Ġāya: A Reconsideration of the Impact of the Rasā’il Iḫwān al-Ṣafā’ on Maslama b. Qāsim al-Qurṭubī,” in Occult Sciences and the Transmission of Knowledge in al-Andalus: A Collection of Essays from the PhilAnd Project, Arabica, 68(5–6): 495–509.
- –––, 2022, “The Ikhwān al-Ṣafā’ on Animals. A Focus on the Non-Narrative Part of Epistle 22,” Journal of Arabic and Islamic Studies, 33: 31–49.
- –––, 2024, “Reconsidering the Influence of the Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Ṣafā’ on Ibn al-Sīd al-Baṭalyawsī’s Kitāb al-Dawā’ir”, in O. Michaelis, S. Schmidtke eds., Religious and Intellectual Diversity in the Islamicate World and Beyond, Essays in Honor of Sarah Stroumsa, 2 vols, Leiden – Boston: Brill, vol. 1, pp. 166–189.
- de Callataÿ, G., Moureau, S., 2015, “Towards the Critical Edition of the Rutbat al-ḥakīm: A Few Preliminary Observations,” Arabica, 62: 385–394.
- –––, 2016, “Again on Maslama Ibn Qāsim al-Qurṭubī, the Ikhwān al-Ṣafā’ and Ibn Khaldūn: New Evidence from Two Manuscripts of Rutbat al-ḥakīm,” Al-Qanṭara, 37(2): 329–372.
- –––, 2017, “A Milestone in the History of Andalusī Bāṭinism: Maslama b. Qāsim al-Qurtubī’s Riḥla in the East,” Histories of Books in the Islamicate World, 5: 86–117.
- Carusi, P., 2000, “Le traité alchimique Rutbat al-hakīm. Quelques notes sur son introduction,” Appendix to “Alchimia islamica e religione: la legittimazione difficile di una scienza della natura,” in C. Baffioni ed., Religion versus Science in Islam: a Medieval and Modern Debate, Oriente Moderno, 80: 491–502.
- Casanova, P., 1915, “Une date astronomique dans les Epītres des Ikhwān as-Safa’,” Journal Asiatique, 5: 5–17.
- Chowdhury, Safaruk, 2021, “Nonhuman Innocents: Theodicies for the Problem of Animal Pain and Suffering,” in S. Chowdhury, Islamic Theology and the Problem of Evil, Cairo – New York: The American University in Cairo Press, pp. 67–98.
- Corbin, H., 1950, “Rituel sabéen et exégèse du rituel,” Eranos Jahrbuch, 19: 181–246.
- –––, 1964, Histoire de la philosophie islamique, I. Des origines jusqu’à la mort d’Averroës, avec la collaboration de Seyyed Hosseïn Nasr et Osman Yahya, Paris: Gallimard.
- Daftary, F., 1998, A Short History of the Ismāʿīlis, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
- –––, 2004, Ismāʿīli Literature, London: Tauris in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- –––, 2007, The Ismāʿīlis. Their History and Doctrines, second edition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- D’Ancona Costa, C., 1996, La casa della sapienza. La trasmissione della metafisica greca e la formazione della filosofia araba, Milano: Guerini e Associati.
- Darraz, Muhd Abdallah, 2012, “Islamic Eco-Cosmology in Ikhwān al-Safā’s View,” Indonesian Journal of Islam and Muslim Societies, 2(1): 133–161.
- De Smet, D., 1999, “Le soleil, roi du ciel, dans la théologie astrale des Frères de la Pureté (Ihwān as-Safā’),” in Le ciel dans les civilisations orientales – Heaven in the Oriental civilizations, (Acta Orientalia Belgica, 12), Bruxelles – Louvain-la-Neuve - Leuven: The Belgian Society for Oriental Studies, pp. 151–160.
- –––, 2014–2015, “La Risāla al-Ǧāmiʿa attribuée aux Ikhwān al-Ṣafā’: un précurseur de l’ismaélisme ṭayyibite?,” in A. Straface, C. De Angelo, and A. Manzo eds., Labor Limae. Atti in onore di Carmela Baffioni, 2 vols, Studi Maġrebini, 12–13, vol. 1: 269–298.
- –––, 2017, “L’auteur des Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’ selon les sources ismaeliennes ṭayyibites,” Shii Studies Review, 1: 151–166.
- –––, 2022, “L’Imam, philosophe et prophète de la cité vertueuse (al-madīna al-fāḍila) d’al-Fārābī, ets-il un imam shiʿite?,” in D. De Smet, M. Sebti eds., Penser avec Avicenne. De l’héritage grec à la réception latine, en hommage à Jules Janssens, Leuven – Paris – Bristol, CT: Peeters: pp. 63–89.
- El-Bizri, Nader, ed., 2008, The Ikhwān al-Safā’ and their Rasā’il, New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies.
- Farhan, Mohammed Jalub, 1999, “Philosophy of Mathematics of Ikhwān al-Safa [sic],” Journal of Islamic Science [Aligarh], 15(1–2): 25–53.
- Fierro, M., 1996, “Bātinism in al-Andalus. Maslama b. Qāsim al-Qurtubī (d.353/964), Author of the Rutbat al-Hakīm and the Ghāyat al-Hakīm (Picatrix),” Studia Islamica, 84(2): 87–109.
- Gobillot, G., 2013, “L’éthique des Ikhwān al-Safā’ dans son rapport au Coran,” in M.A. Amir-Moezzi ed., Islam: identité et altérité. Hommage à Guy Monnôt, o.p., Brepols: Turnhout, pp. 197–245.
- Goldziher, I., 1910, “Über die Benennung der ”Ichwan al-safa“,” Der Islam, 1: 22–26.
- Hamdani, Abbas, 1978, “Abu Hayyan al-Tawhidi and the Brethren of Purity,” International Journal of Middle Eastern Studies, 9(3): 345–353.
- –––, 1979, “An Early Fatimid Source on the Time and Authorship of the Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’,” Arabica, 26: 62–75.
- –––, 1996, “A Critique of Paul Casanova’s Dating of the Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’,” in F. Daftary ed., Medieval Ismaʿili History and Thought, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 145–152.
- –––, 1999, “Brethren of Purity, a Secret Society for the Establishment of the Fatimid Caliphate: New Evidence for the Early Dating of their Enciclopædia,” in M. Barrucand ed., L’Egypte fatimide son art et son histoire, Paris: Presses de l’Université Paris-Sorbonne, pp. 73–82.
- –––, 2008, The Arrangement of the Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’ and the Problem of Interpolations, in N. El-Bizri ed., The Ikhwān al-Safā’ and their Rasā’il, New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies, pp. 83–100.
- Heck, P.L., 2008, Doubts about the Religious Community (Milla) in al-Fārābī and the Brethren of Purity, in P. Adamson ed., In the Age of al-Fārābī: Arabic Philosophy in the Fourth/Tenth Century, London-Turin: The Warburg Institute-Nino Aragno Editore, pp. 195–213.
- Hijab, Muhammad Farid, 1982, Al-falsafa al-siyāsiyya ʿinda Ikhwān al-Safā’, s.l.: Al-hay’a al-misriyya al-ʿāmma li ’l-kitāb.
- Kacimi, Mourad, 2014a, “Estudio de la introducción de la Rutbat al-ḥakīm. Analisis de su relación con las Rasā’il de los Ijwān al-Ṣafā’”, Revista del Instituto Egipcio de Estudios Islámicos, 42: 13–46.
- –––, 2014b, “La relación de Maslama al-Maŷrīṭī con las obras Rasāʼil Ijwān al-Ṣafā’, Risālat al-ŷāmiʿa, Rutbat al-ḥakīm y Gāyat al-ḥakīm,” Anaquel de Estudios Árabes, 25: 29–44.
- –––, 2015, “Reflexiones sobre la relación de la Risālat ǧāmiʿat al-ǧāmiʿa con los Iḫwān al-Safā’,” eHumanista/IVITRA, 8: 328–338.
- –––, 2016, “The Sufi Thought in the Rasa’il Ihwan al-Safa’,” Med/Trans, 4: 1–13.
- –––, 2017, “El pensamiento baṭinī en al-Andalus: reflexiones a partir de la Rutbat al-ḥakīm y la Gāyat al-ḥakīm (s. IV H./X E.C.),” Estudios sobre patrimonio, cultura y ciencias medievales, 19: 729–752.
- –––, 2019, “Los Ijwān al-safā’ contra el estado abasí. Acción política en relación con los diversos estados de su época,” Al-Qantara: Revista de Estudios Árabes, 40(2): 355–384.
- –––, 2024, “En torno a la identidad religiosa de los autores de las Rasā’il Iḫwān al-Ṣafā’ (siglos III-IV/IX-X),” Miscelánea de estudios árabes y hebraicos, Sección Árabe-Islam, 73: 189–216.
- Kraemer, J. L., 1986, Philosophy in the Renaissance of Islam. Abū Sulaymān al-Sijistānī and his Circle, Leiden: Brill.
- –––, 1987, “The Jihad of the Falasifa,” Jerusalem Studies in Arabic and Islam, 10: 288–324.
- –––, 1992, Humanism in the Renaissance of Islam. The Cultural Revival during the Buyid Age, Leiden-New York-Köln: Brill.
- Kraus, P., 1986, Jabir ibn Hayyan. Contribution à l’histoire des idées scientifiques dans l’Islam. Jabir et la science grecque, Paris: Les Belles Lettres (anast. repr.).
- Krinis, E., 2013, “Al-Risāla al-Jāmiʿa and its Judeo-Arabic Manuscript,” in M. A. Amir-Moezzi ed., Islam: identité et altérité. Hommage à Guy Monnot, o.p., Turnhout: Brepols, pp. 311–329.
- –––, 2016, “Cyclical Time in the Ismāʿīlī Circle of Ikhwān al-ṣafā’ (Tenth Century) and in Early Jewish Kabbalists Circles (Thirteenth and Fourteenth Centuries),” Studia Islamica, 111(1): 20–108.
- Lewis, B., 1943, “An Epistle on Manual Crafts,” Islamic Culture, 17: 141–151.
- Lory, P., 2018, La dignité de l’homme, face aux anges, aux animaux et aux djinns, Paris: Albin Michel.
- Madelung, W., 2018, “Maslama al-Qurtubī’s Contribution to the Shaping of the Encyclopedia of the Ikhwān al-Safā’,” in A. Straface et al. ed., Labor limae. Atti in onore di Carmela Baffioni, 2 vols, Studi Maġrebini, 12–13, vol. 1: 403–417.
- Madelung in print, “The Fatimid Attitude toward the Umayyad Caliphate as Reflected in the Sermons of Abū ʿAbd Allāh al-Shīʿī and the Attitude of the Ikhwān al-Safā’”. Paper presented at the International Conference “Fatimids and Umayyads: Competing Caliphates”, London, The Institute of Ismaili Studies, 23–25 September 2016.
- Marquet, Y., 1961, “La place du travail dans la hiérarchie ismaʿílienne d’après L’encyclopédie des Frères de la Pureté,” Arabica, 8: 225–237.
- –––, 1962, “Imamat, resurrection et hiérarchie selon les Ikhwan as-Safa,” Revue des Etudes islamiques, 30: 49–142.
- –––, 1966, “Sabéens et Iḫwān al-Safā’,” Studia Islamica, 24: 35–80.
- –––, 1967, “Sabéens et Iḫwān al-Safā’,” Studia Islamica, 25: 77–109.
- –––, 1968, “Ikhwān al-Safā,” in Encyclopedia of Islam, New Edition, III, Leiden: Brill, 1071–1076.
- –––, 1972, “Les cycles de la souveraineté selon les épītres des Iḫwān al-Safā’,” Studia Islamica, 36: 47–69.
- –––, 1973, La philosophie des Ihwan as-Safā’: l’imām et la société, (Travaux et documents N° 1), Dakar: Université de Dakar, Faculté des Lettres et Sciences Humaines, Departement d’arabe.
- –––, 1975, La philosophie des Ihwan al-Safa’, Alger: Etudes et Documents.
- –––, 1977, “Ihwān al-safā’, Ismaïliens et Qarmates,” Arabica, 24: 233–257.
- –––, 1978, “910 en Ifrîqiyā: Une épītre des Iḫwān aṣ-Ṣafā”, Bulletin d’Études Orientales, 30: 61–73.
- –––, 1981, “Les Ihwan al-Safā’ et l’Ismaïlisme,” in Convegno sugli Ihwan al-Safa’, Roma: Accademia nazionale dei Lincei, pp. 69–96.
- –––, 1985, “Les Épītres des Ikhwān as-Safā’, œuvre ismaïlienne,” Studia Islamica, 61: 57–79.
- –––, 1988, La philosophie des alchimistes et l’alchimie des philosophes. Jābir ibn Hayyān et les «Frères de la Pureté», Paris: Maisonneuve et Larose.
- –––, 1992, “La détermination astrale de l’évolution selon les Frères de la Pureté,” Bulletin des Études Orientales (Damas), 44: 127–146.
- –––, 1998, “La réponse ismaïlienne au schisme qarmate,” Arabica, 45: 1–21.
- Massignon, L., 1913, “Sur la date de la composition des »Rasāïl Ikhwān al Safa«,” Der Islam, 4: 324.
- Mattila, J., 2016, “The Philosophical Worship of the Ikhwān al-Safā’,” Journal of Islamic Studies, 27: 17–38.
- –––, 2019, “The Animal Fable of the Ikhwān al-Ṣafāʾ in Context: The Ontological and Moral Status of Animals in Early Islamic Thought,” in R. Mattila, S. Ito, and S. Fink eds., Animals and their Relation to Gods, Humans and Things in the Ancient World, Wiesbaden: Springer, pp. 345–366.
- Maukola, I., 2009, “Creation in Miniature: Varieties on the Microcosm in the Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safā’,” Studia Orientalia, 107: 229–256.
- Michot, Y.J., 2008, Misled and Misleading... Yet Central in their Influence: Ibn Taymiyya’s Views on the Ikhwān al-Safā’, in N. El-Bizri ed., The Ikhwān al-Safā’ and their Rasā’il, New York: Oxford University Press in Association with the Institute of Ismaili Studies, pp. 139–179.
- Nagy, A., 1897, Die philosophischen Abhandlungen des Jaʿqūb ben Ishāq al-Kindī, Münster: Aschendorffschen Buchhandlung.
- Netton, I.R., 1989, Allah Transcendent. Studies in the Structure and Semiotics of Islamic Philosophy, Theology and Cosmology, Richmond: Curzon Press.
- –––, 1991, Muslim Neoplatonists. An Introduction to the Thought of the Brethren of Purity, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
- –––, 1996, “Foreign Influences and Recurring Ismāʿīli Motifs in Rasā’il of the Brethren of Purity,” in I.R. Netton, Seek Knowledge: Thought and Travel in the House of Islam, London – New York: Routledge Curzon, pp. 27–41.
- –––, 2009, “Private Caves and Public Islands,” in M. Elkaisy-Freimuth, J.M. Dillon eds., The Afterlife of the Platonic Soul: Reflections of Platonic Psychology in the Monotheistic Religions, Leiden – Boston: Brill, pp. 107–120.
- Nokso-Koivisto, I., 2011, “Summarized Beauty: the Microcosm-Macrocosm Analogy and Islamic Aesthetic,” Studia Orientalia, 111: 251–269.
- Poonawala, I., 2015, “Wealth and Poverty in the Qur’an and Traditions of the Prophet, and How Those Concepts are Reflected in the Rasā’il Ikhwān al-Safa’,” Journal of Shiʿa Islamic Studies, 8(3): 263–287.
- Raymond, H., 2014, “Le tribunal des animaux en Islam (IVe-Xe siècle),” Arabica, 61(1–2): 116–152.
- Reymond, P.-L., 2011, “La question de la mentalité à travers la démarche des Ihwān al-Safā’ dans la 17e nuit du Kitāb al-Imtāʿ wa-l-muʿānasa d’Abū Hayyān al-Tawhīdī,” Bulletin d’Etudes Orientales, 60: 123–144; summaries in French, Arabic and English on pp. 319–320.
- Robinson, J.T., 2021, “The ‘Secret of the Heavens’ and the ‘Secret of Number’: Immanuel of Rome’s Mathematical Supercommentaries on Abraham Ibn Ezra in His Commentary on Qohelet 5:7 and 7:27,” Aleph, 21(2): 279–308.
- Rudolph, U., 2005, Islamische Philosophie. Von den Anfängen bis zur Gegenwart, München: Beck.
- Saccone, C., 2007, “Il «retto sentiero» (‘sirāt mustaqīm’) e la via dell’intelletto: sapienza umana e sapienza divina nell’Islam,” Divus Thomas, 110(3): 37–75.
- Saif, L., 2019, “Ikhwān al-Ṣafā’s Religious Reform and Magic: Beyond the Ismaʿili Hypothesis,” Journal of Islamic Studies, 30(1): 34–68.
- –––, 2020, “A Study of the Ikhwān al-Ṣafā”s Epistle on Magic, the Longer Version (52b),” in L. Saif et al. ed., Islamicate Occult Sciences in Theory and Practice, Leiden: Brill, pp. 162–206.
- Stern, S.M., 1946, “The Authorship of the Epistles of the Ikhwan-as-Safa,” Islamic Culture, 20: 367–372.
- –––, 1961, “Ismāʿīlīs and Qarmaṭians,” in C. Cahen ed., L’Élaboration de l’Islam, Colloque de Strasbourg, 12–14 June 1959, Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1961, pp. 99–108.
- –––, 1964, “New Information about the Authors of the ‘Epistles of the Sincere Brethren’,” Islamic Studies, 3: 405–428.
- Stroumsa, S., 2003, “Philosopher-King or Philosopher-Courtier? Theory and Reality in the Falāsifa’s Place in Islamic Society,” in C. de la Puente ed., Identidades marginales, (Estudios onomástico-biográficos de al-Andalus, XIII), Madrid: Consejo Superior de Investigaciones Cientificas, pp. 433–459.
- Tāmir, ʿArif, 1983/1403H., Ibn Sīnā fī marābiʿ Ikhwān al-Safā’, Beirut: Mu’assasa ʿIzz al-Dīn li’l-Tibāʿa wa’l-nashr.
- Tibawi, A.L., 1955, “Ikhwān as-Safa and their Rasā’il. A Critical Review of a Century and a Half of Research,” Islamic Quarterly, 2: 28–46.
- –––, 1978, “Further Studies on Ikhwān as-Safa,” Islamic Quarterly, (20–22): 57–67.
- Vaulx d’Arcy, G. de, 2016, Les Épītres des Frères en Pureté (Rasā’il Iḫwān aṣ-ṣafā) une pensée de la totalité. Etablissement de la paternité historique et commentaire philosophique de l’ouvrage, 2 vols. Thèse dirigée par M. Rashed, Doctorat de Philosophie, Université Paris IV – Sorbonne École doctorale V (Concepts et langage), soutenue le 19 novembre 2016.
- –––, 2018, “« Nul ne sera sauvé si tous ne le sont ». Le complémentarisme des Iḫwān al-Ṣafā. Contribution à la théologie des religions,” MIDEO — Mélanges de l’Institut Dominicain d’Etudes Orientales, 33: 137–181.
- –––, 2019b, “La 17e nuit d’at-Tawhīdī. Réfutation d’une hérésie menaçante, les Épītres des Frères en Pureté,” Revue des mondes musulmans et de la Méditerranee, 146(2-2019). doi:10.4000/remmm/13122 [Vaulx d’Arcy 2019b available online]
- –––, 2019c, “Aḥmad b. al-Ṭayyib al-Saraḫsī, réviseur de l’Introduction arithmétique de Nicomaque de Gérase et rédacteur des Rasā’il Iḫwān al-Ṣafā’,” Arabic Sciences and Philosophy, 29: 261–283.
- –––, 2020, “Trouble dans le genre : le rhinocéros est un oiseau ! Les débuts islamiques de l’anthropozoologie,” in Brémont A. et al. ed., Appréhender les catégories zoologiques dans les sociétés du passé, Anthropozoologica, 55(18): 257–268.
- –––, 2021–2022, “Arabic Zoology and the Tasḫīr Question,” Mélanges de l’Université Saint-Joseph, 69.
- –––, 2023. “The Paradox of Creation. Theology of (De)nature and Physics of Worship in the 3rd/9th Century Kalām and Falsafa,” Quaderni di Studi Arabi, 18(1–2): 304–332.
- Vernet Ginés, J., 1990, “Las obras biológicas de Aristóteles en árabe: el evolucionismo en Ibn Jaldun,” in A. Martínez Lorca ed., Ensayos sobre la filosofía en al-Andalus, Barcelona: Editorial Anthropos, pp. 187–193.
- Villanueva-Romero, D., 2020, “Antispeciesism and Environmentalism in the Spanish Fable: The Case of José Antonio Jáuregui’s Juicio a los Humanos,” in M. Carretero-González ed., Spanish Thinking about Animals, East Lansing: The Michigan State University Press, pp. 21–32.
- Yasien Mohamed, 2006, “The Classical Islamic Concept of Work and the Craft,” Journal for Semitics: Tydskrif vir Semitistiek, 15(1): 130–145.
Academic Tools
How to cite this entry. Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society. Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.
Other Internet Resources
- Islamic Philosophy Online
- Ikhwān al-Safā’, entry by Ian R. Netton, in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Ikhwān al-Safā’, entry by Diana Steigerwald in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- The Rasail Ikhwan as-Safa, at Ismaili.NET