Latin American Philosophy: Metaphilosophical Foundations
A salient feature of Latin American philosophy is its early engagement in reflection about its nature and significance—indeed, its quality and the very possibility of its existence. The result of this reflection has been substantial debates about issues that are of interest not only to Latin American philosophy but to metaphilosophy in general. For they concern the kinds of intellectual inquiry that may count as philosophical. This essay assesses those debates.
- 1. Preliminaries
- 2. What Is Latin American Philosophy?
- 3. The Issue of the Name
- Bibliography
- Academic Tools
- Other Internet Resources
- Related Entries
1. Preliminaries
The nature of philosophy in Latin America first drew the attention of philosophically-minded thinkers in the early nineteenth century, when the region began to develop into nations independent from Spain. But it acquired greater significance with the birth of contemporary academic philosophy in the following century, ultimately taking center stage in Latin American philosophy during the second half of the 20th century, where we still find it today. Often motivated by discomfort with mainstream conceptions of philosophy, inquiry into the nature of Latin American philosophy has involved a number of sub-questions about its existence, originality, authenticity, significance, and role in culture and society. The search for answers has led to reflection on what philosophy is (or should be), as a practice, and as an academic discipline. Thus many Latin American philosophers have devoted their attention to the philosophy of Latin American philosophy, and therefore, to metaphilosophy (understood as in Williamson 2007, p. ix). Somewhat paradoxically, many of those engaged in such metaphilosophical inquiry have shown skepticism about whether there is a philosophy that can rightly be called ‘Latin American.’ Others have recast an old, reductive conception of Latin American philosophy that ascribes to it a certain limited socio-political role. But as discussed in what follows, there is also a third group made up of philosophers whose views about the nature and quality of Latin American philosophy turns out to be neither skeptical nor reductionist in any of the ways to be considered here.
1.1 Two Types of Philosophy
Academic philosophy, or autonomous philosophy as practiced in the West since the Enlightenment, did not begin in Latin America until the first half of the twentieth century. Initially, the reigning philosophical paradigm in the region was Scholasticism. That medieval style of philosophy prevailed during the colonial period, which extended roughly from the early sixteenth century to the early nineteenth century. Mainly confined to rehearsing the doctrines of classical and medieval European philosophers, Latin American Scholasticism was not to be challenged until the eighteenth century, when the theories of the Enlightenment and the rise of modern philosophy began to be known in the American colonies of Spain and Portugal.
Parallel to these philosophical developments, a non-academic type of philosophy consistently prospered in Latin America from the sixteenth century to the present. It comprises philosophical positions expressed in essay format, a hybrid genre cultivated by political and religious leaders, scientists, and literary figures among others. Interested in the intersection of philosophy with literature, religion, and politics, non-academic philosophical thinkers made significant contributions to the intellectual history of Latin America. As may be expected, however, the line separating academic and non-academic philosophy is not always sharp. Although it’s clear that a work such as the Labyrinth of Solitude, by the Mexican writer and diplomat Octavio Paz (1914–1998)[1] falls within the latter, and Lógica viva (Living Logic), by Uruguayan philosopher Carlos Vaz Ferreira (1872–1958) falls within the former, there are many borderline cases. Consider Lascasianism: first developed by the Dominican friar and theologian Bartolomé de las Casas (Spanish-born, 1474–1566) in colonial times, the doctrine is still influential in the work of Peruvian Gustavo Guttiérrez and other contemporary liberation theologians. It advocates a perfectionist version of Roman Catholic ethics according to which the ways of life that should be promoted are those that make people more human—a thesis consistent with las Casas’ 1552 vindication of the humanity of Amerindians (i.e., their personhood). Since Lascasianism has philosophical grounds and implications but is a product of amateur philosophers, it stands out as a prime borderline case between academic and non-academic philosophy.
1.2 Origins
When did philosophy begin in Latin America? Any answer to this question would depend in part to whether one is asking about the beginning of academic or non-academic philosophy. There is consensus that some form of academic philosophy, mostly connected with teaching, existed during the colonial period. An example of a successful work from this early period is Lógica mexicana, a textbook by the Mexican Antonio Rubio (1548–1615) widely used at the time, even in Spain. But it was not until the early twentieth century that philosophy acquired contemporary scholarly dimensions, including standard institutional manifestations.
An interesting metaphilosophical issue related to the origin of Latin American philosophy is whether the philosophical thought of Pre-Colombian cultures also belongs in the non-academic tradition. Needless to say, pre-Columbian thought unfolds in ways that seem utterly alien to our current standards about the form, content, or method method typical of philosophical work. But compliance with any such standards falls short of being a necessary condition for a work to count as philosophical. After all, the works of Pythagoras and the other Pre-Socratics are quite unorthodox in those respects yet considered philosophical. And contemporary examples too are not far to seek. Wittgenstein immediately comes to mind. A number of Latin American philosophers are now prepared to agree with Peruvian Francisco Miró Quesada that “[i]n a broad sense, philosophy has always existed in Latin America. The Maya and the Inca had thought that, without abusing the terms, may be considered of philosophical character….” (1978, p. 75, my translation). Textual evidence of the existence of philosophical thought among the Aztecs has been provided and analyzed by a number of experts. For example, Bernardino de Sahagún (1499–1590), a Spanish friar turned into amateur ethnologist, and contemporary philosophers such as Mexican Miguel León Portilla (1963) and American James Maffie (2009, 2014).
Nuccetelli (2011) considers pre-Columbian works of philosophical import to be part of Latin American proto-philosophy of the non-academic variety. Gracia’s (2008) understanding of Latin American philosophy as ethnic philosophy (more on this later) can also accommodate pre-Columbian philosophical works within that discipline. But Gracia (especially in his 2010) defers taking a position on whether works such as the Maya folk-cosmology in the Popol Vuh count as Latin American philosophy until proper historical work can provide more stable and widely accepted answers about what falls within that ethnic philosophy and what doesn’t.
2. What Is Latin American Philosophy?
As noted above, in contemporary Latin American philosophy lively metaphilosophical debates, recognized as such by its participants, are a frequent occurrence. The Peruvian Augusto Salazar Bondy (1925–1974) held that such debates belong to “the philosophy of philosophy” (1968, p. 13). He also divided the issues at stake into three categories, descriptive, prescriptive, or identity issues (1968, p. 11), a classification that is for the most part still current. One exception is that, today, questions about whether a philosophy is “original, genuine, or peculiar” are not strictly descriptive. For these predicates seem both descriptive and evaluative, and therefore analogous to others now considered thick moral predicates, such as ‘cruel,’ ‘loyal,’ and the like.
2.1 Some Main Descriptive Questions
The principal purely descriptive question in those debates concerns whether philosophy exists as a practice or discipline in Latin America. When answered in the affirmative, a related question is when did it begin? There is consensus that the practice of philosophy sin más (as such—i.e., for its own sake, autonomous of non-philosophical interests) is an early twentieth-century phenomenon. But, understood in a broader sense, it dates from the colonial period. Thus, some take Latin American philosophy to be a contemporary phenomenon (e.g., Miró Quesada 1974, p. 75), while others trace it back to the sixteenth century (e.g., Gracia et al. 1995, p. 462; Hurtado 2007, p. 47). The disagreement, however, is only apparent, since as noted by Francisco Romero one can acknowledge the colonial origins of (broad) philosophy while noting “the prevalence [then] of pedagogical over philosophical concerns with regard to creativity and even the re-thinking of one’s ideas and doctrines” (1941, p. 12, see also his 1943, p. 127).
The descriptive question about the existence of a Latin American (academic) philosophy can be sharpened by breaking it down into smaller questions concerning the truth of each of the following claims:
- Philosophy exists in Latin America as a practice or discipline autonomous from the sciences, theology, literature, politics, and education.
- There are stable philosophical traditions and communities in the region, of the sort commonly found in major centers of Western philosophy.
- Philosophy has acquired professional and institutional status according to current Western standards (i.e., it is properly represented in educational systems, learned societies, associations, journals, presses, etc.).
2.1.1 Philosophy’s Autonomy and “Normalcy”
Since the early twentieth century, there has been a strong endorsement of claim (I) (Alberini 1927; Romero 1943; Miró Quesada 1978; Moulines 2010). But critics are more cautious about previous periods, pointing out that during the colonial period Latin American philosophy was not autonomous from education. During the nineteenth century, as clearly evident in the work of Latin American positivists, philosophical concerns had close connections to political and social interests. In fact, up to about the 1910s, there was room for skepticism about all three claims. Between the 1910s and the 40s, a generation of philosophers known as the fundadores (‘Founders’) strove to develop philosophy in Latin America as an autonomous discipline within academia, with the usual professional organizations and institutions. It was clearly owing to their efforts that philosophy became a practice in their universities analogous to what their peers were doing at the time in major Western centers of scholarship. For the first time since the Wars of Independence and the national organization that followed (roughly, l810–1898), philosophy began to be studied for its own sake. Moreover, it became a professional activity with recognition in the wider community. Through all of these developments, the Founders’ efforts bore fruit in establishing philosophical “normalcy” (maturity). Philosophers of the next generation strove to make the transformations stable. The Argentine Eduardo Rabossi (1930–2005) observes that Latin American philosophy developed relatively quickly compared to philosophy in Europe, since although Latin America followed European models, it was not until the nineteenth century that Europe itself acquired its own philosophical “normalcy” (1994, p. 36).
Be that as it may, by the 1940s not only (I) but also (III) above seemed true, as suggested by Rabossi’s 1994 vivid narrative of the vicissitudes faced by Alejandro Korn (1860–1936) and other Argentinean Founders in their effort to create a Facultad de Filosofía y Letras (College of Liberal Arts) at the Universidad Nacional de Buenos Aires.
2.1.2 The New Skeptics
Given a current view that we may call ‘new skepticism,’ however, claim (II) is false: Latin American philosophy still lacks inner and outer dialogue of the sort needed to develop stable philosophical traditions and communities. Ezcurdia (2003), García-Ramírez (2011), Hurtado (2006, 2007), Pereda (2006), and Rabossi (1994, 2008) are all new skeptics committed to denying some version of (II) on the grounds that Latin American philosophy faces what some of them refer to as an “invisibility” problem. Latin American philosophy is invisible because it has these problems
- Internal Dialogue Problem (IDP): There is no regular philosophical dialogue among Latin American philosophers, and
- External Dialogue Problem (EDP): There is no regular philosophical dialogue between Latin American philosophers and their Western peers.
The new skeptics mostly take the occurrence of an IDP for granted, devoting little effort to providing reliable evidence for it. And when available, the evidence is often difficult to test. A notable exception is Pereda 2006, which points out the lack of sufficient reference to Latin American publications in the numerous contributions by Latin Americans to the Enciclopedia iberoamericana de filosofía (a multi-volume reference work whose first volume appeared in 1987). Other adduced evidence is anecdotal, generally appealing to widespread occurrence of an IDP observed at conferences, learned societies, etc. Narratives to this effect commonly describe Latin American philosophers as intellectuals who fail to engage in the study and discussion of their own traditions, which they perceive as uninteresting, of poor quality, or disenfranchising. For example, adopting Enrique Dussel’s 1998 center/periphery distinction, Rabossi (2008, pp. 102ff.; see also his 1994) tells us that the Latin American philosopher is a “periphery philosopher,” with the self-image of a ‘guacho’ (slang for ‘orphan,’ or even ‘street urchin’). The guacho not only fails to acknowledge his own “philosophical parents,” but doesn’t want to know about them at all: “he doesn’t take them into account, he doesn’t read them, he is not even interested in criticizing their defects or limitations; for him, his own philosophical past doesn’t exist” (2008, p. 103, my translation). Without awareness of his own philosophical past and dialog with regional peers, the Latin American philosopher can have neither philosophical traditions nor genuine philosophical communities. A related claim is made by Hurtado (2006, pp. 206ff.; 2007. pp. 24ff.), for whom the IDP arises for Mexican philosophy, and by extension for Latin American philosophy, owing to the fact that many of its practitioners have followed a “modernizing model.” Among the numerous unwelcome traits of this model are the tendencies of its followers to form small groups and spend most of their time trying to learn some imported philosophy, citing only foreign philosophers without paying much attention to regional peers. Those who adopt this model proceed to study the latest modern tradition, which uncritically replaces previous ones. At the end of the day, in Latin American philosophy “…each modernizing movement got lost for the upcoming movement…” (Hurtado 2006, p. 206), and there are neither traditions nor stable communities of dialogue. “But the foreign philosophers,” laments Hurtado, “even those who visit our countries to deliver talks, very rarely quote us in their work. There is therefore no genuine dialogue…” (Hurtado 2006, p. 205). For Hurtado, in addition to the IDP, Latin American philosophy faces the EDP. And of the two problems, the IDP is the “central” one, thus the EDP appears to depend on the IDP (see also García-Ramírez 2011, and compare Ezcurdia 2003). In any event, on this view, Latin American philosophers will continue to face the IDP “unless we create a genuine critical dialogue among ourselves and simultaneously exercise a constantly renewed memory of past dialogues” (2006, p. 210). Until then, claim (II) is false.
But the new skeptics, confident that both problems, the IDP and EDP, can be resolved invariably offer a list of suggestions about how to do that. There is, however, considerable unacknowledged overlap in such “repair manuals,” which suggests that the new skeptics fail to establish among themselves an internal philosophical dialogue whose very absence from Latin American philosophy they see as a problem. If this ad hominem is strong, then the new skeptics’ challenge to claim (II) is not without problems of its own. For the argument charges that new skepticism appears itself to suffer from the very flaw it criticizes in Latin American philosophy: namely, the new skeptic omits not just establishing a dialogue with, but even acknowledging, the works by other Latin American philosophers on the topic at issue. And although some new skeptics do make some such references (e.g., García-Ramírez 2011), these are limited to the work of those who are also new skeptics. But not all Latin American philosophers face the IDP, since as we shall see next there is abundant textual evidence that the metaphilosophical questions of concern here have generated intense dialogue and discernible skeptical and anti-skeptical traditions. For this reason, claim (II)—viz., that there are stable philosophical traditions and communities in the region, of the sort commonly found in major centers of Western philosophy— has not yet been shown false.
2.2 Some Main Normative Questions
Answers to the normative questions concerning whether there is, or could be, a Latin American philosophy that is original, authentic, peculiar, or in some other ways distinctive constitute a wide philosophical spectrum, with what may be called ‘strong universalism’ at one extreme, ‘strong distinctivism’ at the other, and ‘middle-way theories’ in between.
2.2.1 Universalism vs. Distinctivism
Strong universalism is the view that all philosophical theories, methods, and topics have an import that is universal rather than relative to regions, persons, groups, or cultures. It conflicts with strong distinctivism, the view that all of philosophy’s theories, methods, and topics represent the point of view of a region, person, group, or culture. The contemporary representatives of universalism in Latin American philosophy are many and have different philosophical orientations (for an overview of classic universalism, see Salazar Bondy 1968, pp. 45ff.). Universalism appears to be what Argentinean Pablo Navarro has in mind when he asserts “Legal philosophy in Latin America does not differ significantly from philosophical studies of the law in the United States, Germany, the UK, or Sweden” (2009, p. 439).[2] Gracia 2000 and Montemayor 2011 associate being a scientifically-minded philosopher with favoring universalism. Perhaps the connection is grounded in some such philosophers’ previous commitment to the objectivity of science, together with their thesis that science is the model for philosophy.
For a classic representative of universalism we need to look no further than the work of the Argentine Risieri Frondizi (1910–1983), who by combining universalism with originalism was led to the skeptical conclusion that, in the late 1940s, only a very small part of philosophy in Latin America deserved to be considered philosophy at all. But as pointed out earlier by his compatriot José Ingenieros (1887–1925), not everything needs to be (indeed we might say, ‘can be’) original in the work of “a true philosopher” (Ingenieros 1914, p. 7). Furthermore, not only is originality a matter of degree but the term ‘original’ is itself ambiguous. It has been used with connotations such as
- Being creative, novel, and autochthonous (Ingenieros 1914).
- Being creative and non-imitative (Cannabrava 1949; Frondizi 1949).
- Being a philosophical product that “makes some degree of contribution to ideas or approaches, with respect to previous works, and is sufficiently discernible as a creation and not a repetition in content. In this sense, an original philosophy is identified by its new conceptual constructions of recognized value” (Salazar Bondy168, p. 100, my translation).
- Being tradition-originating (Hurtado 2007).
Putting aside Hurtado’s more idiosyncratic understanding of the term and Ingenieros’s too permissive understanding as a synonymous of ‘autochthonous,’ we have:
A philosophical work is original just in case it makes some degree of contribution to philosophy by being creative, non-imitative, or novel with respect to previous works.
2.2.2 The Originality Problem
We’ll now consider two positions, Frondizi 1949 and Pereda 2000, each committed to holding that Latin American academic philosophy fails to be sufficiently original in the above sense. Frondizi’s commitment to this thesis is explicit: he concludes that based on the evidence, only 10% of philosophy ‘as such’ in Latin America is original. Since the works of non-academic philosophers are excluded from this evidence, as a result Latin American philosophy is devoid of significant history, theories, methods, and number of creative practitioners. Nuccetelli 2003 responds to this skeptical view by arguing that by contrast with academic philosophers in Latin America, the non-academic philosophers have offered the more original philosophical positions. Furthermore, in other parts of the world contributions by non-academics who did not practice philosophy for its own sake are often counted as philosophy, as exemplified by works of Hume, Bentham, Mill, Saint Simon, Marx and many others. If this is correct, then Frondizi’s criterion turns out to be too demanding. In addition, Gracia (2003) notes that in no other ethnic philosophy (more on this later) is originality considered a necessary condition for having philosophy
Pereda’s recent work also shows he thinks that there is an originality problem facing Latin American philosophy, an skeptical view presupposed by his claim that philosophy in the region is “invisible” (i.e., suffers from the IDP and EDP mentioned above). Like Frondizi, Pereda first praises the work of Latin American essayists, and even takes it to be a model that philosophy must emulate in order to overcome its invisibility problems. But to be a model that needs emulation is one thing, to count as Latin American philosophy quite another. Since Pereda also locates non-academic philosophy somewhere else, as a result, he runs head-on into a conclusion similar to Frondizi’s skepticism about the features of Latin American philosophy. Such skepticism is inevitable because on Pereda’s view, Latin American philosophy suffers from the “arrogant reasoning” of its practitioners, which fuels the epistemic vices of “nationalist enthusiasm” (in the case of distinctivists) or “subaltern fervor” and “craving for novelty” (in the case of universalists). Such vices, and ultimately arrogant reasoning itself, are to be blamed for the internal and external invisibility of Latin American philosophy.
It can now be shown that these alleged vices of universalists, if substantiated, would raise an originality challenge to Latin America philosophy. After all, universalism has many representatives of a great variety of persuasions (Gracia and Jaksić 1986, p. 214; Miró Quesada 1978, p. 76; Salazar Bondy 1968, pp. 49ff.). If universalists are driven by subaltern fervor and a craving for novelty, then they need perforce to devote considerable time and effort to assimilating the latest fads (something they have done, according to Hurtado’s 2006 critique of the modernizing model). Since producing work that is to a significant degree original requires considerable time and effort, there would be empirical constraints on those philosophers’ capability to produce original work.
Therefore, it seems that the invisibility problem is closely connected with the originality problem. But although all new skeptics think there is an invisibility problem for Latin American philosophy, they disagree about what to make of the originality problem. For new skeptic Maite Ezcurdia (2003), it does arise. On her view, of four kinds of originality she identifies as desirable in philosophy (viz., interpretative, argumentative, problem-making, and problem-solving), Latin American philosophy comes out as having interpretative originality, yet lacking originality of the other three kinds. In particular, Ezcurdia contends that an improvement in problem-solving originality is needed for fixing the EDP, which would in turn lead to a solution to the IDP. On the other hand, Eduardo García-Ramírez (2011, p. 13) dismisses the originality problem but writes: “even though there is enough originality, most Latin American philosophy is haunted by the two proceedings of arrogant reasoning: internal visibility is a function of the external partly because Latin American philosophy is not used to thinking on its own.” Questions arise, however, as to how could there be enough originality in a philosophy that’s not used to thinking on its own?
2.2.3 The Authenticity Problem
According to distinctivists, a chief distinguishing characteristic of Latin American philosophy is—or should be—authenticity, a feature of any “philosophical product that, like any other cultural product has integrity and is devoid of falsity or pretense. In this sense, we say, for example, that Kant’s philosophy is authentic, but spiritism is pseudo-philosophy” (Salazar Bondy 1968, pp. 100–101, my translation). Salazar (1968, p. 101) and (Hurtado 2006, p. 209) distinguish authenticity from peculiarity, the regional coloring of a philosophical product that is characteristically Latin American. A philosophical work may be peculiar by virtue of discussing a Latin American theme or by virtue of being the product of a Latin American author, even when it could lack authenticity, originality, or both. At the same time, it could be original and/or authentic without being peculiar. Since a full account of such conceptual inter-relations goes beyond our present purpose, let’s stipulate that a Latin American philosophy is
- Original just in case it is creative, non-imitative, or novel;
- Authentic just in case it is genuine or non-spurious; and
- Peculiar just in case it is characteristically Latin American.
As pointed out by Salazar, feature (3) is the cheapest of all: it can easily be obtained by a work whose topic, or even author, is relevantly related to Latin America. Although, as we’ll soon see, peculiarity may be what some distinctivists actually have in mind, more often they care most about authenticity—holding that originality will come ‘for añadidura’ (as an addition).
An early proposal to develop a peculiar Latin American philosophy is that of the Argentine Juan Bautista Alberdi (1810–1884) in his “Ideas….” This short newspaper article, published in Montevideo in 1840, offers advice about how to develop a high school course in philosophy to be taught at the Colegio de Humanidades (School of Humanities). It recommends that the course be aimed at “instruct[ing] the youth in the principles that reside in the conscience of our societies” (1840, p. 97, my translation). On this view, Latin American philosophy should be devoted, not to abstract metaphysics, but rather to applied philosophy, focusing on the social and political issues of the day in the newly independent nations of the region. But Alberdi’s article also ventures into metaphilosophical issues that were far beyond politics and diplomacy, his areas of expertise—notoriously opining, among other things, that it was for Europe, not Latin America, to do the theoretical philosophical thinking (1840, p. 95). Not to be reprinted until the following century, this article is unlikely to have had the influence ascribed to it by some distinctivists of the 1940s and their followers. The point is made forcefully by the Uruguayan Arturo Ardao (1912–2003), a well-known historian of Latin American philosophy who contends that the article “came to have influence in Latin America in the context of the philosophical innovations of the 1940s, precisely a year after its centennial. Its most decisive apologist turned out to be the magisterial philosopher Gaos in Mexico ” (1991, p. xxiii, my translation). Arturo Roig also regards the twentieth-century fascination with Alberdi’s “Ideas” as an ideological coincidence. He writes:
Gaos’s opinions and theses conferred on Alberdi’s text a significance more vast [than its actual one], which goes beyond the topic of a ‘national philosophy’ that was the framework within which the text was evaluated in Argentina. It also ascribed to it a scope unimagined by Alberdi. It appears, rather, that Alberdian historicist circumstantialism ended up coinciding with Mexican circumstantialism… (Roig 1981b, p. 1, my translation)
For a more contemporary vindication of features of Latin American philosophy akin to peculiarity, we’ll need to turn to some of the middle-way theories below. But first, let’s consider the two main strands of extreme distinctivism in Latin American philosophy, ‘the critical theory’ and ‘circumstantialism’ (also known as ‘critical view,’ and ‘culturalism’ respectively; see e.g., Gracia and Jaksić 1986).
The critical theory is a hybrid that includes theses from early twentieth century Marxists as well as the views of contemporary ‘liberation philosophers,’ who in turn combine Marxist ideas with European doctrines from French structuralism, the Frankfurt School, and other sources. Abundant textual evidence suggests that, for the critical theorist, Latin America philosophy commonly lacks originality, authenticity, and/or peculiarity. Thus, an early representative of the view laments that:
All the thinkers of our America have been educated in European schools. The spirit of the race is not felt in their work. The continent’s intellectual production lacks its distinguishing traits. It does not have an original profile. Hispanic-American thought is generally only a rhapsody composed from the motifs and elements of European thought. To prove this, one needs only review the work of the highest representatives of the Indo-Iberian intellect. (Mariátegui 1925, p. 113, my translation)
Similarly, a critical theorist of the 1940s regards Brazilian (and, by extension, Latin American) philosophy as lacking originality, authenticity and peculiarity by virtue of its creators’ “colonial mentality,” a situation that would persist until Latin America has won “complete independence—economic, and cultural—from the imperialistic powers” (Coutinho 1943, pp. 187–188). Analogous arguments were offered later by Salazar, for whom Latin American philosophy had been, from its colonial beginnings, only “a thought of the upper class or of a refined oligarchical elite, when it has not corresponded openly to waves of foreign economic and political influence. In all these cases underdevelopment and domination are influential” (1969, p. 241). Endorsing this line of reasoning, Roig declares that the work of Founders such as the Peruvian Alejandro Deustua (1849–1945) is “a prime example of the uprooting and the alienation in Latin American thought denounced so vehemently by Augusto Salazar Bondy” (1976, p. 251).
But it seems reductionist at best to hold that cultural dependence and economic underdevelopment always determine a philosophy’s shortcomings in the features relevant here. A prime counterexample is the ethics of las Casas mentioned above, which is original, authentic, and peculiar, though developed under extreme cultural and economic dependence (for more on this, see Nuccetelli 2013). Furthermore, the critical theory also faces the following ad hominem objections:
- Since the critical theorist usually belongs to the upper class in Latin American societies, which on her own view are incapable of producing a philosophy with features (1)–(3), the critical theory itself lacks (1)–(3) and should be rejected.
- The critical theorist usually borrows from European traditions such as Marxism, existentialism, structuralism, and the Frankfurt School. But borrowed traditions are, on her own view, incapable of generating an authentic Latin American philosophy. It follows that the critical theory is not authentic and should be rejected.
Objections along these lines (e.g., Gracia 2003 and Hurtado 2007), together with its vulnerability to counterexamples, make the critical theory implausible.
There is, however, another distinctivist theory that might be plausible: circumstantialism. Famously expounded by the Mexican Leopoldo Zea (1912–2004), its main concern is authenticity. Putting aside its contention that an authentic philosophy is bound to acquire originality and peculiarity at some point, here is circumstantialism’s main argument:
- All philosophical works are authentic in that they invariably show the cultural circumstance of their production.
- Therefore, all Latin American philosophical works show the cultural circumstance of their production.
- Therefore, all Latin American philosophical works are authentic.
Consistent with this argument, the circumstantialist maintains,
The abstract issues [of philosophy] will have to be seen from the Latin American man’s own circumstance. Each man will see in such issues what is closest to his own circumstance. He will look at these issues from the standpoint of his own interests, and those interests will be determined by his way of life, his abilities and inabilities, in a word, by his own circumstance. In the case of Latin America, his contribution to the philosophy of such issues will be permeated by the Latin American circumstance. Hence, when we [Latin Americans] address abstract issues, we shall formulate them as issues of our own. Even though being, God, etc., are issues appropriate for every man, the solution to them will be given from a Latin American standpoint. (Zea 1948, p. 226)
In this way, the circumstantialist appears to have dissolved the alleged conflict between universalism and distinctivism. For, given the above argument, the following claims are all compatible:
- There is an authentic Latin American philosophy.
- The problems and methods of philosophy are universal.
- Philosophers’ ‘circumstances’ always shape their theories and methods.
But the soundness of the cirumstantialist argument hinges on its premise 1. This is a very strong claim which entails not only that (a) the context of discovery (or creation) is to some degree apparent in any philosophical theory, so that all theories are peculiar in the above sense, but also that (b) such context renders them authentic. Yet (a) is at the very least controversial, given that it is not obvious what is Greek about Aristotle’s theory of the syllogism or German about Kant’s categorical imperative (see Nuccetelli 2003, but compare Monahan 2005). Moreover, (a) may entail peculiarity, not authenticity. For the latter, the circumstantialist needs (b), a claim for which no sound argument is in the offing. In addition, as argued in Gracia 2003, there is an irresolvable problem for anyone attempting to specify what’s necessary and sufficient for being a Latin American cultural circumstance, as opposed to the circumstances of other cultures. And no less difficult would be the task of tracing the connections between philosophical theories and culture in Latin America, given the bewildering diversity of cultures that have flourished there.
2.2.4 Reductionism about Latin American Philosophy
A number of recent contributors to the debate about the nature of Latin American philosophy have contended that philosophical inquiry in the discipline should focus on some historical, social, and/or economic issues relevant to Latin Americans and their descendants in the USA. For instance, according to José Antonio Orosco (2016) Mexican American philosophy and Latin American philosophy as practice in the United States should focus on developing the perspective of the Mexican people and the Latin American people respectively. On his view, the success of these disciplines hinges on their ability to deal with “questions about [Mexican or Latino] identity, power, and citizenship in the United States,” which may have an impact on “U.S. American political and social life” (Orosco 2016: 27). Since such issues belong to applied ethics and political philosophy, his recommendation has direct reductionist connotations assuming that he thinks that they are the only issues that matter, or should matter, to practitioners of Mexican/Latin American philosophy in the USA. But perhaps that connotation is not what Orosco has in mind since that would defeat his own inquiry into the nature of Mexican American and Latin American philosophy, both issues of metaphilosophy. Silva Grant’s 2015 proposal is analogously reductionist. Elizabeth Millán Brusslan (2015) has objected to it on the grounds that it is too exclusionary. After all, many philosophical works that are content-related to Latin American philosophy but do not engage in such social, historical, and/or economic issues would be left out of Latin American philosophy. For Grant, the sole task of this field is conducting inquiry into the struggle of Latin Americans against colonialism. Nuccetelli (2018) rejects any such proposal as a kind of thorough-going relativism because different theorists would disagree about the issues that need be the focus of Latin American philosophy. In addition, she argues that such metaphilosophical reductionism has bad practical consequences because it may contribute to an existing bias against Latin American philosophers in the USA according to which they commonly make either false or unsupported empirical claims about issues that belong to other humanities or the social sciences. Susanna Siegel (2014) recommends against contributing to this bias while suggesting that philosophical questions are distinct from questions of other humanities or the social sciences. On different grounds, many practitioners of Latin American philosophers have noted the existence of such a widespread bias (e.g., Covarrubias 2015, Gracia 2000, Mendieta 1999, Sánchez 2011, and Vargas 2007, 2010).
2.3 Middle-Way Theories
Middle-way theories reject both strong universalism and strong distinctivism. If successful, they would avoid the problems facing each of those extremes—which, as we saw above, are skepticism about Latin American philosophy (in strong universalism) and ungrounded assumptions (in strong distinctivism). Here we’ll briefly consider three recent middle-way positions. The first two agree that it would be possible to provide examples of sufficient conditions for a work to count as Latin American philosophy. The position discussed last undertakes the more ambitious project of proposing a set of conditions that are necessary and jointly sufficient.
2.3.1 Gracia’s Ethnic-Philosophy Account
What we may call ‘the ethnic-philosophy account’ (Gracia’s 2003, 2008) is a neo-Wittgensteinian view holding that Latin American philosophy (and more broadly, Hispanic and Latino/a philosophy) is
[T]he philosophy of an ethnos, and insofar as it is so, and members of ethne do not necessarily share features in common, then what the philosophy of a particular ethnos is exactly will not require any features in common with other philosophies outside the ethnos or even within the ethnos throughout its history. This, I claim, is the best way of understanding the unity of Latin American philosophy. (Gracia 2008, p. 140)
On this account, being the philosophy of the Latin American ethnos is sufficient for counting as Latin American philosophy. At the same time, the account holds that it is not possible to provide conditions that are necessary and jointly sufficient for being an instance of this ethnic philosophy. No such conditions are to be had, even in the case of ‘Spanish philosophy,’ another ethnic philosophy for which no necessary and sufficient conditions of inclusion can be offered, even though it appears identifiable in nationality terms—a conclusion suggested by the fact that ‘Spanish philosophy’ commonly includes figures such as “Seneca and Averroes, philosophers who lived long before the Spanish nation was constituted as a political reality, and whose relationship to this nation, as we have known it since the sixteenth century, is less than tenuous” (Gracia 2003, p. 57).
This conception of Latin American philosophy as an ethnic philosophy is inspired by Wittgenstein’s ‘family resemblances’ theory for concepts such as ‘game’ and ‘funny.’ For example, there is no distinguishing feature that all games have in common in virtue of which they are games. Rather, there are resemblances between activities we call ‘games’ that are like the resemblances between members of a single family. Similarly, there are no distinguishing properties of an ethnic philosophy but numerous properties that would each be a sufficient condition for belonging to it. This seems to entail that that an ethnic philosophy can be categorized in a variety of ways, given that its identity hinges at least in part on the adopted “selective point of view” with regard to its properties. Some cases illustrating the claim come readily to mind. Consider Picasso’s works. They may be legitimately categorized as French under one selective point of view, and as Spanish under another. Thus, whether they fall under one or the other is at least in part contingent upon a selective point of view (Gracia 2003, p. 65). Likewise, it is possible that certain philosophical works belong to Latin American philosophy under one selective point of view, but not under another. Thus, whether Latin American philosophy turns out to be thin or robust would then itself be contingent, at least in part, upon which selective point of view one were to adopt. In short, since the concept ‘Latin American philosophy’ is relevantly analogous to concepts such as ‘game’ or ‘funny,’ there are no necessary and sufficient conditions for individuating Latin American philosophy; but a variety of selective criteria are possible. Each such criterion would be legitimate, provided that it captured a contextually determined, sufficient condition for being an instance of Latin American philosophy. Here is how the ethnic-philosophy theorist spells out his view on this matter
In a context in which all texts are in English and have American authors except for one, who is Uruguayan, the origin of the author could be sufficient to identify the text as belonging to Latin American philosophy. In a situation in which we have a series of Latin texts published in Spain, but one of which was written by an author who spent the greatest part of his life in Mexico, we could identify this text as Latin American. (Gracia 2003, p. 64)
One of the advantages of this account is its flexibility. For it entails that Latin American philosophy can accommodate whatever works meet an appropriate contextually determined condition, whether they be nonstandard works such as those of las Casas and Guttiérrez, or mainstream ones such as those of Newton da Costa or C. Ulises Moulines (more on this below). The account is also capable of accommodating the fact that some works seem characteristically Latin American while others have a universal import. Furthermore, it allows one to classify, e.g., Kant’s categorical imperative as German philosophy in a context where an author’s place of origin is relevant, and as universal deontology in a context where birthplace is not relevant.
The main challenge for this view is how to avoid an anything-goes form of metaphilosophical relativism. Gracia (2003, p. 66) has sought to eliminate this threat by emphasizing that it is not only a contextually determined, selective point of view that matters for individuating ethnic philosophies. Reality also has a role, possibly in connection with history, which Gracia invokes to explain the nature of “philosophical texts.” On his view, these are “historical entities, the product of historical beings in particular times and places whose identities are linked to the context in which they were produced and which, for that reason, depend on them” (2003, p. 65). Metaphilosophical relativists can, however, welcome this appeal to history, though they would further insist that it is not only philosophical texts but also the truth of philosophical theories that’s similarly contingent upon historical context. In fact, more than a mere logical possibility, relativism of this sort is by now a strong twentieth century tradition in the philosophy of science (see, e.g., Kuhn 1962, especially chapter 10).
2.3.2 Moulines’s Compromise Account
Also a middle way between universalism and distinctivism is Moulines’s 2010 position. Like Gracia’s account, it vindicates only sufficient conditions for being an instance of Latin American philosophy. But unlike Gracia’s account, Moulines’s does not argue against the possibility of conditions that are both necessary and jointly sufficient. His positive proposal consists of four sufficient conditions that, on his view, a number of recent works meet—namely, they are universal in the sense that they use concepts and provide arguments that are intended to be universally valid; (2) they have been developed by Latin American authors; (3) they have been originally devised, at least partially, in some Latin American countries; and (4) they have found widespread interest both in and outside Latin America.
Satisfying (1) through (4) is considered sufficient for a work to be “an instantiation of ‘Latin American philosophy’” (Moulines 2010, p. 460). Moulines’s sample of such instances includes several brands of theories and/or methods developed by contemporary Latin American philosophers such as paraconsistent logic (by Brazilian Newton da Costa and his collaborators), formal deontic logic (by Argentinean Carlos Alchourrón and Eugenio Bulygin), belief revision (in part by Alchourrón), scientific realism (by Argentinean Mario Bunge), a historical approach to the foundations of physics (by Chilean Roberto Torreti), and structuralist theory of science (by Venezuelan Moulines and his collaborators).
According to Moulines, conditions (1) through (4) express an understanding of Latin American philosophy that is “‘universalist’ as much as ‘distinctivist’” (2010, p. 460). A quick look at them suggests that (1) is relevant to universalism, (2) and (3) to distinctivism, and (4) to neither because it is neutral, though it bears on the external invisibility problem mentioned above. But note that(2) and (3) are distinctivist only in terms of ‘peculiarity’—which, as pointed out earlier, is the cheapest of the distinctive properties at issue on this debate.
2.3.3 Nuccetelli’s Applied-Philosophy Account
Another mid-way position to be considered here was developed in Nuccetelli 2002 and 2009. It proposes a set of conditions that are taken to be both necessary and jointly sufficient for being an instance of a characteristically Latin American philosophy—namely, that any qualifying work must
- Contain philosophical arguments or methods that are sufficiently original, and
- Be sensitive to a Latin America context.
Any work satisfying (1) and (2) would count as characteristically Latin American in Nuccetelli’s sense. She further contends that there is a robust body of philosophical work in Latin America that satisfies these conditions. It is mostly devoted to issues of moral, social, and political philosophy and includes the works of both, non-academic and academic philosophers. Thus construed, Latin American philosophy comes out as a branch of applied philosophy and its existence is consistent with that of universal philosophy—which is grounded in a variety of traditions of Western philosophy and devoted to problems that have universal import such as knowledge and skepticism, the nature of consciousness, moral reasoning, and the existence and attributes of God. A Latin American philosopher may cultivate either universal philosophy or some branch of applied philosophy, including Latin American philosophy. From the time of the Founders to the present, there has been a long list of those who in fact did both.
3. The Issue of the Name
A final note on the issue of the name: Latin American philosophers have expressed a number of different preferences about what to call the field. The standard name preferred here has been ‘Latin American philosophy.’ But there are other options, depending on whether ‘thought’ takes the place of ‘philosophy,’ and/or ‘Iberoamerican,’ ‘Hispanic,’ ‘Hispanic-American’ or ‘Latino/a’ (among other qualifiers) takes the place of ‘Latin American.’ Keeping in mind that not all replacements would be semantically equivalent (a topic revisited later), note that the rationale for using ‘thought’ in lieu of ‘philosophy’ is to do justice to the breadth of philosophical developments in Latin America—which, as we’ve seen, includes a vast corpus of non-standard, non-academic philosophical works. There is no common rationale for substituting any of the above qualifiers for ‘Latin American.’ But each proposed qualifier (including ‘Latin American’) inherits a problem faced by the proper name from which it derives. The problem may be semantic or pragmatic, where
- A semantic problem arises for the use of a term in the absence of satisfactory criteria for determining its meaning or reference, and
- A pragmatic problem arises for the use of a term in the presence of morally, politically, or socially unacceptable connotations associated with that term.
As an illustration, let’s consider the term preferred here, ‘Latin American philosophy.’ Its qualifier derives from ‘Latin America,’ which appears to suffer from both types of problem. With few exceptions (e.g., Oliver 1998), those who have recently reflected on this term go beyond geography and politics to consider also factors such as culture and history in order to determine this term’s meaning and reference. But it has proved difficult to find criteria that avoid semantic problems such as
- The term is too broad since ‘Latin America,’ when used literally and directly, refers to certain people and territories which are not ordinarily taken to be Latin American (e.g., the Quebecois).
- The term is too narrow since ‘Latin America,’ when used literally and directly, does not refer to peoples and territories that are ordinarily taken to be Latin American (e.g., the indigenous peoples of Latin America).
- The term is both too broad and too narrow since ‘Latin America’ faces both of the previous problems.
Jorge Gracia (2011a, p. 8) offers a way around these problems by taking ‘Latin America’ to refer to “everything in the Americas that is not American (U.S.) or Canadian.” This extensional, negative criterion gets things right provided it assumes a cultural understanding of ‘American (U.S.)’ and ‘Canadian.’ Without that assumption, the criterion would be both too narrow and too broad, for it would exclude Puerto Rico, which is politically part of the U.S., and include St. Pierre and Miquelon, which are French islands off the coast of Canada. But Gracia (2011a, p. 8) seems to have in mind the relevant cultural understanding of the term, because he notes that “those parts of the Caribbean and South America that were French, Dutch, or English colonies, such as Haiti and Jamaica” are not part of Latin America (i.e., culturally understood).
On the other hand, Eduardo Rabossi (2003) explicitly provides a set of intensional criteria, which he appears to consider necessary and sufficient for falling under the reference of ‘Latin America.’ According to them, the term denotes certain “states” of North, Central, and South America by virtue of their sharing “a common political origin (Spanish/Portuguese conquest), a similar linguistic heritage (Spanish/Portuguese), a dominant religion (Catholicism), and comparable predicaments vis à vis local, regional, and international affairs” (Rabossi 2003, p. 507). Rabossi’s criteria, which are more restrictive, avoid being too broad, but face the problem of being too narrow, which makes them unsatisfactory.
Guillermo Hurtado’s (2010) reflection on the adequacy of the qualifier ‘Latin American’ illustrates the pragmatic problem mentioned above. First, Hurtado too takes ‘Latin America’ to denote a culturally specific region of the Americas, one individuated by appeal to language: viz., being a region of the Americas that mostly speaks Spanish, Portuguese or French. Perhaps aware of the problem of being too broad, Hurtado attempts to avoid it by excluding Quebec from the designation of ‘Latin America’ on the seemingly ad hoc ground that the region is surrounded by mostly ‘Anglo-Saxon’ Canada. In any case, his account of ‘Latin American’ and ‘the Latin American’ appears to point to a pragmatic problem arising from some facts about those terms’ introduction into public discourse. According to Hurtado, there is historical evidence that they were introduced into public discourse in the late nineteenth century by the French, who did so in order to advance their national interest in dealing with the Latin and Catholic nations of the Americas (as opposed to the Protestant and ‘Anglo-Saxon’ nations). Once these terms had caught on in thought and language, their role in discourse was unaffected by the defeat of the French in the region, except for the fact that ‘Latin America’ came instead to be just “an ideal of union among the nations that compose it” (Hurtado 2010, p. 11, my translation and emphasis). At the end of the day, however, Hurtado continues to use these terms without explaining why we should do so, given that, according to his own story, they were introduced for colonialist purposes—and therefore face the pragmatic problem.[3] In addition, given this account, it would seem that those terms now refer to nothing objective at all.
Be that as it may, let’s now consider some of the other options. ‘Iberoamerican’ and ‘Hispanic American’ are the closest relatives of ‘Latin American.’ Neither of these alternatives is problem free, since they inherit the pragmatic problem facing the nouns from whence they derive, ‘Iberia’ and ‘Hispania.’ Each of these ancient proper names designates the European peninsula today divided into Spain and Portugal. Thus, taken literally, each has connotations unacceptable to the descendants of the victims of these countries’ colonial policies in the Americas.
On the other hand, ‘Hispanic philosophy’ and ‘Latino/a philosophy’ are more recent terms whose semantic features are not yet fully settled by usage. Roughly, ‘Hispanic philosophy’ may include Iberian philosophy too (Gracia 2000), while ‘Latino/a philosophy’ is the philosophy of or about the descendants of Latin Americans abroad, especially in the United States (Gracia 2011b). As noted above in the cases of ‘Iberoamerican’ and ‘Hispanic American,’ both ‘Hispanic’ and ‘Latino/a’ also appear to have inherited the pragmatic problem for the proper nouns from which each derives (it should now be obvious to the reader what those problems are).
But it may be that no such pragmatic problem matters after all for justifying the current use of ‘Latin American’ or some of the alternative terms. That would be so if the reference of the proper name from which any such term derives is direct, in the sense that it is not mediated by the term’s descriptive meaning.[4] On this account, the justification for using the term needs only appeal to linguistic convention.
Bibliography
- Alberdi, J. B., 1840, “Ideas para presidir la confección del curso de filosofía contemporánea,” in Escritos póstumos, vol. 15, pp. 603–619, Buenos Aires: Imp. Juan Bautista Alberdi; page reference is to the reprint in Terán 1988.
- Alberini, C., 1927, “Contemporary Philosophic Tendencies in South America,” The Monist, 37: 328–334.
- Ardao, A., 1963, “Assimilation and Transformation of Positivism in Latin America,” Journal of the History of Ideas, 24: 515–522.
- –––, 1979, “Historia y evolución de las ideas filosóficas en América Latina,” Proceedings of the IX Inter-American Congress of Philosophy, 1: 61–69.
- –––, 1991, “Prólogo,” in Zea 1991, pp. ix–xxviii.
- Beuchot, M., 1996, The History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico, Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press.
- –––, 2005, “The Study of Philosophy’s History in Mexico as a Foundation for Doing Mexican Philosophy,” in Salles and Millán 2005, pp. 109–130.
- Cannabrava, E., 1949, “Present Tendencies in Latin American Philosophy,” Journal of Philosophy, 5: 113–119.
- Cerutti-Guldberg, H., 1989, “Actual Situation and Perspectives of Latin American Philosophy for Liberation,” Philosophical Forum, 20: 43–61.
- Covarrubias, J., 2015, “Report on the 2015 Fleishhacker Chair Lecture Series and Latin American Philosophy,” APA Newsletter on Hispanic/Latino Issues in Philosophy, 18(1): 3–l8.
- Coutinho, A., 1943, “Some Considerations on the Problem of Philosophy in Brazil,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 4: 186–193.
- Cruz Revueltas, J. C. (ed.), 2003, La filosofía en América Latina como problema, Mexico City: Publicaciones Cruz.
- Devés Valdés, E., 2000, Del Ariel de Rodó a la CEPAL (1900–1950), Buenos Aires: Editorial Biblos.
- Dussel, E. D., 1998, Ética de la liberación en la edad de la globalización y la exclusión, Madrid: Trotta.
- Ezcurdia, M., 2003, “Originalidad y presencia,” in Cruz Revueltas 2003, pp. 196–202.
- Fornet-Betancourt, R., 2010, “De la Significación de la filosofía latinoamericana para la superación del eurocentrismo,” Revista de Filosofía, 65: 7–19.
- Frondizi, R., 1943a. “Tendencies in Contemporary Latin-American Philosophy,” in Inter-American Intellectual Interchange, Austin: Institute of Latin American Studies, University of Texas, pp. 35–48.
- –––, 1943b. “Contemporary Argentine Philosophy,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 4: 180–187.
- –––, 1949, “Is There an Ibero-American Philosophy?” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 9: 345–355.
- Gaos, J., 1957, Sobre Ortega y Gasset y otros trabajos de historia de las ideas en España y la América española, Mexico City: Imp. Universitaria.
- García-Ramírez, E., 2011, “On the Invisibility Problem of Latin American Philosophy,” APA Newsletter on Hispanic/Latino Issues in Philosophy, 2: 10–17.
- Garrido, M., N. R. Orringer, L. M. Valdés and M. M. Valdés, eds., 2009, El legado filosófico español e hispanoamericano del siglo XX, Madrid: Cátedra.
- Gilson, G., 2006. “The Project of Exact Philosophy: An Interview with Mario Bunge, Frothingham Chair of Logic and Metaphysics, McGill University, Toronto, Canada,” APA Newsletter on Hispanic/Latino Issues in Philosophy, 1: 8–10.
- Gracia, J. J. E. (ed.), 1986, Latin American Philosophy in the Twentieth Century, Buffalo: Prometheus Books.
- –––, 1988–89. “Latin American Philosophy Today,” Philosophical Forum, 1–2: 4–32.
- –––, 1993, “Hispanic Philosophy: Its Beginning and Golden Age,” Review of Metaphysics, 46: 475–502.
- –––, 1996, “Foreword: The Origins of Hispanic Philosophy,” The History of Philosophy in Colonial Mexico, M. Beuchot, pp. xi–xxx, Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press.
- –––, 2000, Hispanic-Latino identity: A Philosophical Perspective, Oxford: Blackwell.
- –––, 2003, “Ethnic Labels and Philosophy: The Case of Latin American Philosophy,” in Mendieta 2003, pp. 57–67.
- –––, 2008, Latinos in America: Philosophy and Social Identity, Oxford: Blackwell.
- –––, 2010, “Latin American Philosophy as Ethnic Philosophy: Response to Susana Nuccetelli,” Inter-American Journal of Philosophy, 1: 44–54.
- ––– (ed.), 2011a, Forging People: Race, Ethnicity, and Nationality in Hispanic American and Latino/a Thought, Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
- –––, 2011b, “Race, Ethnicity, and Nationality in Hispanic American and Latino/a Thought,” in Gracia 2011a, pp. 1–28.
- Gracia, J. J. et al., 1995, “Latin American philosophy,” in The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, T. Honderich (ed.), pp. 23–27, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Gracia, J. J. and I. Jaksić, 1986, “Introduction,” Part III in Gracia 1986, pp. 209–216.
- Grant, S., 2015, “Why the Struggle Against Coloniality Is Paramount to Latin American Philosophy?” APA Newsletter on Hispanic/Latino Issues in Philosophy, 18(1): 8–12.
- Guttiérrez, G., 1993, Las Casas: In Search of the Poor Jesus Christ, Maryknoll, NY: Orbis.
- Hurtado, G., 2006, “Two Models of Latin American Philosophy,” Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 3: 204–213.
- –––, 2007, El búho y la serpiente: ensayos sobre la filosofía en México en el siglo XX, Mexico City: UNAM.
- –––, 2010, “El diálogo filosófico interamericano como un diálogo para la democracia,” Inter-American Journal of Philosophy, 1: 1–17.
- Ingenieros, J., 1914, La evolución de las ideas argentinas, Buenos Aires: Revista de la Universidad de Buenos Aires, Tomo XXVII; page reference is to Buenos Aires: Ediciones L. J. Rosso, 1937.
- Kolescov, M., 1990, “El pensamiento filosófico de América latina en la búsqueda de su autenticidad,” Islas, 96: 42–52.
- Kuhn, T. S., 1962, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Las Casas, B. de, 1550 [1992], Bartolomé de las Casas: The Only Way, H. Rand Parish (ed.), Mahwah, New Jersey: Paulist Press.
- León-Portilla, M., 1963, Aztec Thought and Culture, Norman: University of Oklahoma Press.
- Maffie, J., 2009, “Pre-Columbian Philosophies,” in Nuccetelli et al. 2009, pp. 9–22.
- –––, 2013, Aztec Philosophy: Understanding a World in Motion, Boulder: University Press of Colorado.
- Marti, O., 1983, “Is There a Latin American Philosophy?” Metaphilosophy, 1: 46–52.
- Mariátegui, J. C., 1925, “Existe un pensamiento hispano-americano?” Repertorio Americano, 17: 113–15. [Available online]
- Mendieta, E., 1999, “Is There Latin American Philosophy?” Philosophy Today, 43: 50–61.
- Mendieta, E. (ed.), 2003, Latin American Philosophy: Currents, Issues, Debates, Bloomington IN: Indiana University Press.
- Millán Brusslan, E. 2015, “Philosophy Born of Colonial Struggle: One Theme or the Whole Story of the Latin American Philosophical Tradition?” APA Newsletter on Hispanic/Latino Issues in Philosophy, 18(1): 13–20.
- Miró Quesada, F., 1974, Despertar y proyecto del filosofar latinoamericano, Mexico City: Fondo de Cultura Económica.
- –––, 1976, El problema de la filosofía latinoamericana, Mexico City: Fondo de Cultura Económica.
- –––, 1978, “Posibilidad y límites de una filosofía lationamericana,” Rev. Fil. Univ. Costa Rica, XVI (43): 75–82.
- Monahan, M. J., 2005, “On the Question of Latin American Philosophy,” APA Newsletter on Hispanic/Latino Issues in Philosophy, 1: 14–18.
- Montemayor, C., 2011, “Engagement and Universality in Latin American Philosophy,” APA Newsletter on Hispanic/Latino Issues in Philosophy, 2: 7–12.
- Moulines, C. U., 2010, “What Is Characteristic of Latin American Philosophy?” Metascience, 19(3): 457–460.
- Navarro, P., 2009, “Deontic Logic and Legal Philosophy,” in Nuccetelli et al. 2009, pp. 439–453.
- Nuccetelli, S., 2001, “‘Hispanics,’ ‘Latinos,’ and ‘Iberoamericans’: Naming or Describing?” Philosophical Forum, 32: 175–188.
- –––, 2002, Latin American Thought: Philosophical Problems and Arguments, Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press.
- –––, 2003, “Is ‘Latin American Thought’ Philosophy?” Metaphilosophy, 4: 524–537.
- –––, 2004, “Reference and Ethnic-Group Terms,” Inquiry, 6: 528–544.
- –––, 2009, “Latin American Philosophy,” in S. Nuccetelli et al. 2009, pp. 343–356.
- –––, 2013, “Latin American Ethics,” in International Encyclopedia of Ethics, H. LaFollette (ed.), Cambridge, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 2970–2979. doi: 10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee648
- –––, 2018, “Latino Philosophy,” in Oxford Handbook of Latino Studies, Illan Stavans (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 199–218. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780190691202.001.0001
- Nuccetelli, S., O. Schutte, and O. Bueno, eds., 2009, Blackwell Companion to Latin American Philosophy, Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
- Nuccetelli, S. and G. Seay, eds., 2004, Latin American Philosophy: An Introduction with Readings, Upper Saddle Brook, New Jersey: Prentice Hall.
- Nuccetelli, S. and R. Stewart, 2009, “Ethnic-Group Terms,” in S. Nuccetelli et al. 2009, pp. 241–252.
- Oliver, A. A., 1998, “Latin American Philosophy,” in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E. Craig (ed.), London: Routledge. [Available online]
- Orosco, J. A., 2016, “The Philosophical Gift of Brown Folks: Mexican American Philosophy in the United States,” APA Newsletter on Hispanic/Latino Issues in Philosophy, 15: 23–28.
- Paz, O., 1961, The Labyrinth of Solitude: Life and Thought in Mexico, New York: Grove Press.
- Pereda, C., 2006, “Latin American Philosophy: Some Vices,” Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 3: 192–203.
- Piossek Prebisch, L., 2008, Argentina: identidad y utopía, Tucumán, Argentina: EDUNT.
- Rabossi, E., 1994, “Filosofar: profesionalismo, profesionalidad, tics, y modales,” Cuadernos de Filosofía; page reference is to the reprint in Cruz Revueltas 2003, pp. 34–44.
- –––, 2003. “Latin American Philosophy,” in The Cambridge History of Philosophy 1870–1945, T. Baldwin (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 507–512.
- –––, 2008, En el comienzo Dios creo el Canon. Biblia berolinensis. Ensayos sobre la condición de la filosofía, Buenos Aires: Gedisa.
- Roig, A., 1976, “The Actual Function of Philosophy in Latin America,” in Gracia 1986, pp. 247–259.
- –––, 1981a, Teoría y crítica del pensamiento latinoamericano, Mexico City: Fondo de Cultura Económica.
- –––. 1981b, “Necesidad y posibilidad de un discurso propio,” in Roig 1981a. [Available online]
- ––– (ed.), 2000, El pensamiento social y político iberoamericano del siglo XIX, Enciclopedia iberoamericana de filosofia, v. 22. Madrid: Editorial Trotta.
- Romero, F., 1941. “Enrique José Varona,” in Romero, Filósofos y problemas, Buenos Aires: Losada, 1956, pp. 1–40.
- –––, 1943, “Tendencias contemporáneas en el pensamiento hispanoamericano,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 2: 127–133.
- –––, 1944, Filosofía de la persona y otros ensayos, Buenos Aires: Losada.
- –––, 1944, “Sobre la filosofia en Iberoamérica,” in Romero 1944, pp. 147–157.
- Sahagún, B. de, 1575–80, The Florentine Codex: General History of the Things of New Spain, Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, 1950–82.
- Salazar Bondy, A., 1967, Historia de las ideas en el Perú contemporáneo. El proceso del pensamiento filosófico, Lima: Francisco Moncloa Editores.
- –––, 1968, ¿Existe una filosofía de nuestra América? Mexico City: Siglo XXI.
- Salles, A. and E. Millán-Zaibert, eds., 2005, The Role of History in Latin American Philosophy: Contemporary Perspectives, Albany, New York: SUNY Press.
- Sánchez, C. A., 2011, “Philosophy and the Post-Immigrant Fear,” Philosophy in the Contemporary World, 18(1): 31–42.
- Siegel, S., 2014, “Reflections on the Use of English and Spanish in Analytic Philosophy,” Informes del Observatorio / Observatorio Reports 006-12/2014EN, Instituto Cervantes, Harvard University.
- Sturm, F. G., 1980, “Dependence and Originality in Iberoamerican Philosophy,” International Philosophical Quarterly, 3: 249–263.
- Terán, O. (ed.), 1988, Alberdi póstumo, Buenos Aires: Puntosur.
- ––– (ed.), 2004, Ideas en el siglo. Intelectuales y cultura en el siglo XX latinoamericano, Buenos Aires: Siglo XXI.
- Vargas, M., 2007, “Real Philosophy, Metaphilosophy, and Metametaphilosophy: On the Plight of Latin American Philosophy,” CR: The New Centennial Review, 3: 51–78.
- –––, 2010, “On the Value of Philosophy: The Latin American Case,” Comparative Philosophy, 1: 33–52.
- Vaz Ferreira, C., 1910, Lógica viva. Moral para intelectuales, Caracas: Editorial Ayacucho, 1979.
- Vila Bormey, M. T., 1987, “El problema de la autenticidad y originalidad de la filosofía lationamericana en el pensamiento de Augusto Salazar Bondy,” Islas, 86: 162–171.
- Villegas, A., 1963, Panorama de la filosofia iberoamericana actual, Buenos Aires: Eudeba,
- Williamson, T., 2007, The Philosophy of Philosophy, Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
- Zea, L., 1942, “En torno a una filosofia americana,” Cuadernos Americanos, 3: 63–78.
- –––, 1948, “The Actual Function of Philosophy in Latin America,” in Gracia 1986, pp. 219–230.
- –––, 1969, La filosofía Americana como filosofía sin más, Mexico City: Siglo XXI.
- –––, 1989, “Identity: A Latin American Philosophical Problem,” Philosophical Forum, 1–2: 33–42.
- –––, 1991, La filosofía como compromiso de liberación, L. Weinberg de Magis and M. Magallon, eds., Caracas: Biblioteca Ayacucho.
Academic Tools
How to cite this entry. Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society. Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.
Other Internet Resources
- Latin American Philosophy
- Projecto Ensayo Hispánico
- “Latin American Philosophy,” entry in the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy